Education Report:
Character Education
Hoover Institution
Transmitting
Moral Wisdom in an Age of the Autonomous Self
How Moral
Education Is Finding Its Way Back into America’s Schools
The
Science of Character Education
A
Communitarian Position on Character Education
Building
Democratic Community: A Radical Approach to Moral Education
Moral
and Ethical Development in a Democratic Society
==============================
Bringing in a New Era in
Character Education (2002)
Edited by William Damon
http://www-hoover.stanford.edu/publications/books/character.html
==============================
Making fundamental moral standards a cornerstone of the educational process
Education in the United States has at last ended its failed experiment with separating the intellectual from the moral—and schools from K–12 to college campuses are increasingly paying attention to students' values and accepting responsibility for students' character. But how can we bring in this new era in character education in a way that makes the right kind of difference to young people? What are the approaches that will provide character education the solid foundation necessary to sustain it now and into the future? What obstacles in our current educational system must we overcome, and what new opportunities can we create? This book provides a unique perspective on what is needed to overcome the remaining impediments and make character education an effective, lasting part of our educational agenda.
Each chapter points out the directions that character education must take today and offers strategies essential for making progress in the field. The expert contributors explain, for instance, how we can pass core values down to the younger generation in ways that will elevate their conduct and their life goals. They reveal why relativism has threatened the moral development of young people in our time—and what we can do to turn this around. And they show the critical importance of reestablishing student morality and character as targets of higher education's central mission.
The authors make a strong case for "moral exemplarity"—actual human examples of moral excellence—as an effective tool of educational practice and describe how stoic "warrior" principles can offer a moral manner of managing one's emotions in times of pressure. Perhaps most important, they clarify the necessity of authority in any moral education endeavor—and show how it is actually a powerful force for both personal freedom and character building.
William Damon is a Hoover Institution senior fellow. He is a professor of education and director of the Center on Adolescence at Stanford University.
Contributors: Marvin W. Berkowitz, Anne Colby, Irving Kristol, F. Clark Power, Arthur J. Schwartz, Nancy Sherman, Christina Hoff Sommers, Lawrence Walker
==============================
Introduction vii
William Damon
Transmitting Moral Wisdom in an Age of the Autonomous Self 1
Arthur J. Schwartz
How Moral Education Is Finding Its Way Back into America’s Schools 23
Christina Hoff Sommers
The Science of Character Education 43
Marvin W. Berkowitz
Moral Exemplarity 65
Lawrence J. Walker
Educating the Stoic Warrior 85
Nancy Sherman
A Communitarian Position on Character Education 113
Amitai Etzioni
Building Democratic Community: A Radical Approach to Moral Education 129
F. Clark Power
Whose Values Anyway? 149
Anne Colby
Moral and Ethical Development in a Democratic Society 173
Irving Kristol
Contributors 183
Index 187
==============================
William
Damon
Genuine
change in a modern educational system usually takes place slowly, if at all; but
we have seen one notable exception to this in recent times. With astonishing
rapidity, education in the United States has ended its failed experiment in
separating the intellectual from the moral and choosing the intellectual as its
only legitimate province. From K-12 schools to college campuses, instructors
are paying attention to students’ values and are accepting responsibility for
promoting students’ character.
By no
means is this an unprecedented approach: indeed, it is a return to the more
comprehensive “whole student” agenda that American schools had dedicated
themselves to during the first three centuries of education in this country.
But during the middle and latter parts of the twentieth century, educators
found themselves embedded in a highly specialized, secular, knowledge-driven,
postmodern world. Most responded by concluding that the moral part of their
traditional mission had become obsolete. Moral relativism was in, in loco
parentis was out. The dominant view held that educators should promote critical
thinking and tolerance which, amazingly, were not viewed as moral values, but
rather as neutral, inert positions outside the contentious realm of value
choices. This thinking was a misconception that caused so many readily apparent
casualties among the young that it was bound to be abandoned sooner or later.
Fortunately the correction has occurred surprisingly quickly. As we enter the
twenty-first century, it is well under way.
As an
advocate for this correction, I have glimpsed the change even at the federal
government level, which typically reacts to rather than induces cultural
trends. At the dawn of the Clinton administration, Secretary of Education
Richard Riley addressed a conference of character educators such as me who were
looking for ways to reintroduce moral messages into the K-12 curriculum. The
secretary supported our aims, but in response to a question commented (I cannot
quote him verbatim after all these years) that he did not see much role for the
federal government or for public schools in such an endeavor, because children’s
values were a private matter that should be reserved for families and churches.
Three
years passed, with widely noted media accounts of youngsters harming themselves
and others through morally misguided choices. In his 1996 State of the Union
Address President Clinton proclaimed that every school in America should teach
character education. He said: “I challenge all our schools to teach character
education, to teach good values and good citizenship.” Secretary Riley’s
Department of Education established a program to support this idea. Four years
later, in the presidential election of 2000, one of the major candidates (the
winning one, in fact) frequently campaigned on a promise to promote character education
in America’s public schools—a pledge that he, now President Bush, has acted
upon since assuming office by tripling federal support for the Education
Department program. I have believed in character education for most of my
working life, but I never thought that I would see it arise as a major campaign
promise in a presidential election, or garner so much support at the highest
reaches of government.
We have
entered a new era in character education, marked by broad public acceptance of
the idea and endorsements by top elected officials from both political parties.
This is a good start, a window of opportunity that could stay open long enough
to allow worthwhile efforts to enter. But all such windows eventually shut if
the worthwhile efforts stall or get pushed aside by less serious ones designed
only to take advantage of the trend. How can we bring in this new era in
character education to make the right kind of difference to the young people in
our schools and colleges? What are the principles and approaches that provide character
education the solid foundation to sustain it now and in the future, so that it
again becomes a lasting part of our educational agenda rather than merely
another trend? What obstacles in our present-day educational system must we
overcome, and what new opportunities can we create? The purpose of this book is
to provide some beginning answers to these questions. The authors are among the
most innovative thinkers in the field today, and in their chapters they offer
original solutions unconstrained by the misconceptions that have derailed moral
instruction in our schools.
Each
chapter puts forth a unique perspective on what is needed in character
education today, but at least two main themes run throughout the volume. The
first is a consensus that fundamental moral standards must be passed along to
the young and that educators at all levels bear a serious obligation to
transmit these core standards to their students.
The
question of “Whose values are these anyway?”—in recent years the battle cry of
those who would keep schools barren of moral guidance—is shown to be moot by
several of the authors. They are our values, the “our” referring to the
worldwide community of responsible adults concerned with the quality and very
futures of the civilizations that their younger citizens will one day inherit.
The second theme that emerges from this volume is a shared determination to get
rid of sterile old oppositions that have paralyzed even some of the best
efforts in this field over the past few decades. Many oppositions have gotten
in the way and must be transcended by a more integrated, inclusive,
all-encompassing approach if real progress is to be made:
Most
parents know that it is essential to raise children to act right and to
exercise good judgment in complex or difficult situations. Every child deserves
to acquire reliable habits and strong
reasoning skills. Children who do not acquire this beneficent combination may
become untrustworthy to themselves, despite whatever good intentions they may
have; or, alternatively, they may become automatons susceptible to malevolent influences
that they cannot screen or evaluate. Strangely, contemporary scholarly
discourse draws lines between the aims of fostering good habits and clear
reasoning about justice and other moral matters.
The
philosopher Bernard Williams1 criticizes
his own field for setting up a false opposition between virtue theory (virtues
simply being the characterological consequence of sustained habit) and justice
theory (which advocates a constant thinking through of procedures that create social
contracts and their implications for fairness). Williams points out that there
should be nothing incompatible about virtue and fairness. Any full moral life
aspires to achieve both. Williams notes that the two moral aims share common
enemies—hypocrisy, a self-serving tendency to rationalize inaction or
compromise, and a willingness (or too often an eagerness) to pursue supposedly
moral ends through immoral means. Compounding philosophy’s confusion, a quirk
in the history of psychology sets habit and reflection in opposition. In the
scientific study of moral development, the two dominant camps for the large
part of the twentieth century were the behaviorist and cognitivist traditions
(the psychoanalytic tradition remaining mostly outside of academia because of
its sparse research base). Behaviorism emphasized the person’s conformity to
rules and the conditioning of habitual modes of conduct; whereas cognitivists
such as Piaget and Kohlberg emphasized the person’s capacity for reasoning and
autonomous judgment.
Dividing
the person in this way may or may not serve the purposes of scientific
study—that is a debate for another occasion—but it is an unmitigated disaster
for education, which must in the end deal with all the components of the
developing youngster. The incredibly fruitless opposition between habit and
reflection has been transplanted from psychology and philosophy to realms of
educational theory and practice, where it has polarized character education
efforts for precious decades. It is time to move beyond this needless argument
and take as our target of moral instruction the whole child—habit and
reflection, virtue and understanding, and every system of judgment, affect,
motivation, conduct, and self-identity that contributes to a child’s present
and future moral life.
Much
rhetoric has been wasted arguing about the locus of the moral sense that we try
to cultivate in every child. Extreme positions proliferate all across the
ideational landscape.Some hold that morality is essentially biological, deeply
rooted in an individual’s genetic code, with the implication that individuals
are born with varying degrees of it. This position leaves us little to do
educationally but spot the bad seeds and get out of the way of the good ones.
Even the question of whether parents matter has been taken seriously in recent
years. At the other extreme, some insist that all moral truth resides in the
community, that excessive individualism is the root of our problems, and the
task of moral educators is to promote cultural transmission and an awareness of
our interdependence. Neither position gives much credence to the age-old ideals
of personal conscience, noble purposes, or inspirational social action.
The
supposed opposition between the individual and the community is a popular myth
based upon degraded versions of culture theory. The idea is that Western
morality (especially the American version) stresses individual rights and
responsibilities, unlike the rest of the world (Japan is often cited as an
example), where a communal orientation prevails. More serious anthropologists2 know that
all such notions exist everywhere. Indeed, how could any society survive
without holding individuals accountable for their actions, recognizing and
protecting their rights (at least to some extent), or establishing some
communal sense of the common good? Societies certainly vary in how they balance
and express these moral orientations, in the degree to which they emphasize one
or the other, and in the cultural traditions that organize them, but morality
is always a matter of individual transactions with communities, and children
must be prepared both to learn from their social settings and to follow their
own consciences when the need arises. For educators, morality means teaching
common values as well as helping every child acquire the kind of personal moral
identity that ultimately will sustain the child’s moral sense in any
situation—joyful or grim, inspiring or corrupting—that the child encounters in
life.
In these
days when public school districts are sued for allowing student choirs to sing
hymns, when valedictorians are forbidden to use the word “God” in their
commencement addresses, and when teachers are reprimanded for wishing students
“Happy Holiday!” before school vacations (I have not invented these incredible
examples), it must be noted that things were not always so in this country. For
most of our history, public education did not distinguish between moral
messages conveyed in a secular package and moral messages conveyed through
stories and sayings from any one of the world’s religious traditions. Far from
banning every expression of religious sentiment, public schools recognized it
(generally in a nonsectarian form) as one source of moral inspiration and
guidance. Schoolbooks were full of uplifting moral, spiritual, and religious
ideas mingled with lessons designed to teach literacy, math, and whatever else
children needed to learn. It was part of what I referred to earlier as the
whole student approach that did whatever it could to foster character as well
as intellect, goodness as well as knowledge, purpose as well as competence.
Starting
with the Progressive Era, and throughout the remainder of the twentieth
century, public education split the secular from the religious, adopting the
former and rejecting the latter. This choice was spurred by pluralism and a
well-intentioned desire to protect children whose families might not share the
beliefs expressed. I do not dismiss such reasons: they are important in
themselves, and all children should learn to understand and respect the civil
liberties concerns that they reflect. But such matters always must be viewed in
the perspective of an overall pedagogical agenda, which in turn must be
tailored to how young people learn.
How do
young people learn moral beliefs and values? This book provides sound answers
to this question, answers based on careful scholarship rather than on
unanalyzed fears or wishful thinking. Some of the insights shared by many
authors in this book are (1) young people learn best through clear
messages—moral relativism and ambivalence leave young minds cold; (2) young
people learn from positive instances of exemplary behavior. A single shining,
in vivo example of virtue is a more powerful teaching tool than scores of
abstract “do not’s”; (3) young people have active, curious minds that eagerly
seek new knowledge. They are not especially fragile, and the real danger is in
turning them off by failing to provide sufficient inspiration, not in
disturbing them with harmful information; and (4) young minds have great
intellectual flexibility—they are capable both of absorbing the traditional
wisdom of their culture and of making smart choices for themselves when they need
to.
I have
never heard of a youngster being harmed by witnessing another person’s
expression of spirituality, even when the form of spirituality is highly
unfamiliar to the child. On the contrary, young people usually are fascinated
and moved by such expressions and the more foreign the forms, the more they are
likely to find them interesting rather than disturbing. The civil liberties
concerns about minority rights and the dangers of theocratic oppression are
adult issues worth teaching at some point, to be sure, but not frontline issues
for the moral instruction of young people, who need to learn far more basic
lessons about core standards such as honesty, compassion, responsibility,
respectfulness, and fairness. Adult-centered concerns should not be used as
justification for censoring a unique and powerful source of positive moral inspiration
from our public schools. It is time to open our public schools once again to
moral ideas set in a variety of religious as well as secular frameworks as well
as to students’ free expressions of spiritual faith.3 Young
people need all the inspiration they can get.
Each
chapter in this book points to directions that character education must take at
this juncture and offers strategies essential for progress. Taken together, the
chapters suggest a comprehensive approach for such progress.
Arthur
Schwartz identifies the starting point of our new era: no longer is the
distracting question “Whose values?” bogging down our character education
efforts. That question has been settled by a consensus throughout our society—a
widespread, tacit agreement that all children should acquire the core values of
civilized living that responsible adults cherish. Now that we can stop wasting
our time on unnecessary uncertainty, we can make progress on the more profound
and difficult question of how we can pass these values down to the younger
generation in ways that will elevate their conduct and their life goals.
Schwartz has his own answers to this that are at the same time innovative and very
old. His suggestions about reintroducing wise maxims in curricula and his
examination of how honor codes should be used in our schools should be required
reading for educators everywhere.
Following
a theme introduced by Schwartz, Christina Hoff Sommers shows why it is
relativism, not indoctrination, that threatens the moral development of young
people in our time. She starts with an example of ambivalence toward the right
or wrong of cheating, an example that would be amusing if it were isolated or
bizarre. Unfortunately, as I have discovered in my own travels through every
level of our educational system, Sommers has given us a revealing glimpse into
a grave malignancy that threatens both the character of our students and the
integrity of our academic institutions (more about this below). Sommers offers
a classic vision of moral education that springs from the principles of
Aristotelean and Augustinian philosophy that is corrective of the laissez-faire
excesses fomented by Rousseau and his legion of modern-day followers. Sommers
shows us the depths to which misguided ideas can take us and offers hope for
the future by describing approaches that can lead us to a better way.
Education,
like medicine, is a field of practice; but, like medicine, it needs a
scientific base in order to weed out ineffective (or even dangerous) practices
from beneficial ones. The subfield of character education has been establishing
a scientific base for some decades, and Marvin Berkowitz provides us with an
up-to-date account of it. Beyond his chapter’s importance as a rare
state-of-the-science statement of what we know from solid evidence, Berkowitz
also makes several key points that reinforce the main themes of this book. He
rejects the false oppositions that have riven the field, creating in the end a
synthesis that should appeal to a wide swath of practitioners (theoreticians
and philosophers are another matter—it is possible that they enjoy the
arguments too much to fully accept any synthesis). Berkowitz also takes pains
to spell out what we don’t know as well as what we do know. This is valuable
for two reasons: first, it speaks for keeping our pedagogical methods open to
change as our scientific base expands; and second, it reminds us to be humble
in whatever approaches we try. Humility is a virtue that character educators
should aim to foster among students as well as to practice themselves.
Lawrence
Walker also takes us through the scientific literature, but with a more
particular purpose in mind. Walker makes the case for an approach based on
actual human examples of moral excellence, an approach that Walker calls moral
exemplarity. The advantages of this approach are similar in both science and
education: it can resolve oppositions of the sort that Berkowitz and others
find futile; and it offers a compelling, indeed captivating, way of
incorporating all the elements of morality that make their way into a human
life. The use of moral examples for scientific study and educational practice
has been explored before, but Walker’s powerful analysis goes beyond previous
writings to reveal the promise and significance of such an approach.
Warriors
ennobled by moral principle are one archetype of exemplars, and Nancy Sherman
shows how stoic principles have shored up the resolve and conduct of heroic
warriors such as Navy Pilot James Stockdale. Sherman’s treatment of stoic
philosophy is subtle and evocative. She shows how stoic principles, when fully
understood, offer a moral manner of managing one’s emotions in times of
pressure. This makes for a unique, invaluable contribution to the moral
education literature that generally avoids the problem of inner emotional
control. Sherman also sees the limits of Stoicism, cautioning that an overly
rigid version may lead to emotional coldness and detachment from the empathic side
of moral response. Her own resolution—“Stoicism with a human face”—bears
implications for character education far beyond the military settings in which
she has worked.
Sherman
notes that she began her service at the Naval Academy with a visit commissioned
by a navy chaplain in the wake of a shocking cheating scandal. I accompanied
her on that visit, and my impressions are still fresh in my mind. Here was a
group of incredibly dedicated officers, faculty, and student-midshipmen torn
apart by an enormous breach in one of the navy’s proudest traditions, its
esteemed honor code. How could such a thing happen? My personal conclusion was
that the ethics behind the code, and the moral bases of rules against cheating,
were not properly understood by students at the Academy, for the simple reason
that they were not being carefully taught. I believe that Professor Sherman’s
ethics course went a long way toward rectifying this situation. That is the
good news. The bad news is that similar and worse problems are prevalent at
schools and colleges across the nation. Almost everywhere, there is a lack of
clarity surrounding cheating. In her chapter, Sommers describes the lack of
clarity shared by faculty and students alike. Tests that faculty distrust or
students dislike do not justify dishonesty as a form of protest. This is not a
legitimate act of civil disobedience, in which a dissenter openly admits to
breaking a rule and bravely accepts society’s sanctions for it. This is instead
a deceptive, self-serving, and furtive bit of behavior, a step down the path to
personal irresponsibility. When teachers tell students that they can’t blame
them for cheating on any tests that are unfair or meaningless, or worse, when
teachers urge students to cheat as a way of boosting teachers’ performance
ratings (as news reports, incredibly, have verified), this is moral
miseducation. It is training students to become dishonest. No ideological
position about testing, competition, or anything else can justify such a
choice. If there were such a thing as educational malpractice, this would be a
prime example.
Clark
Power’s discussion of a cheating incident in a school where he worked provides
another illustration of the deeply entrenched confusion surrounding this moral
issue. Students struggle to sort out the difference between cooperation and
dishonesty.Oneyoung girl believes she is being an altruist in the image of
Mother Teresa by sharing her work with a friend! Students need the guidance
that can teach them respect for school codes but many teachers, Power writes,
merely “facilitate [rather than] instruct . . . [and] ask questions [rather
than] provide answers.” Although Power is more sympathetic to this kind of teaching
than I, his chapter offers a poignant account of how his own mentor, Lawrence
Kohlberg, moved to a more sociological position toward the end of his life,
adopting Durkheimian insights about establishing a structure of moral authority
for moral education. In this more traditional vision, a teacher becomes an
elder collaborator who transmits cultural wisdom. Power’s designation of this
approach as countercultural can only be seen as ironic. He notes, for example,
that Western culture is open to change and thus often countercultural with itself.
Passing Western culture along means communicating this dynamic spirit, not a
bad way to orient the younger generation to the excitement of democracy. But
the culture that Power really counters is the prevailing atmosphere of our
public schools. Here Power is in closer agreement with the other authors in
this book, all of whom seek to elevate the desultory moral atmosphere that too
many students today encounter.
Amitai
Etzioni’s Communitarian Network has played a key role in creating
a nationwide discourse among educators dedicated to character education and in
bringing this discourse to the attention of policy makers long before the idea
became politically popular. The network organized a number of influential
conferences in the 1990s, including the early White House meeting that I
referred to above. In his chapter for this book, Etzioni charts out the “communitarian
position” on character education, a position that centers on (1) affirming core
values, (2) promoting empathy within the child and of bonds of attachment
between the child and others, and (3) imparting disciplinary standards that
emanate from legitimate authority, but that also become part of the child’s own
internal set of chosen beliefs.
In line
with other authors in this book, Etzioni deals with the question of “whose
values?” by pointing out that moral values are not at all arbitrary (“Values do
not fly on their own wings,” he writes). Etzioni looks to social institutions
such as the family, schools, voluntary associations, and places of worship for
reference points regarding the values that we must pass along to the young. His
position places schools squarely within, rather than apart from, their
communities. Our schools never should have become the sheltered enclaves of
expertise and overspecialization that resulted in their neglect of moral values
and character for much of the past century. Etzioni reminds educators that cultivation
of students’ character is necessary even for the academic parts of their
mission: “You cannot fill a vessel that has yet to be cast.” In her chapter,
Anne Colby fights the good fight for reestablishing student morality and
character as targets of higher education’s central mission. When they first
were founded, most colleges and universities dedicated themselves to fostering
students’ moral development, but as higher education has drifted toward
increasing specialization and compartmentalization, the original whole student
agenda has been discarded.
Those who
would recapture the old ground have met with great resistance. Colby takes on
each point of resistance with unassailable logic, effectively demolishing every
familiar objection that has been raised against character education at the
post-high-school level. Colby’s chapter will inspire and protect those in
higher education who are bold and caring enough to concern themselves with
students’ moral lives, yet find themselves besieged by those who would keep the
ivory tower knowledge-pure and value-free.
For the
present volume, Irving Kristol has revised an incisive statement that he
originally wrote during the 1970s,4 the
heyday of valuesneutral approaches to moral education. His chapter reminds us
that a child’s individual development requires guidance from people and
institutions with firm moral bearings. Like Sommers, he rejects the Rousseauian
view, so prevalent in schools today, that the job of adults is simply to get
out of children’s way and allow intrinsic goodness to emerge naturally. Kristol
points to the necessity of authority in any moral educational endeavor. He uses
the concept of authority advisedly. First, he explicitly refers to legitimate
authority. Second, he distinguishes legitimate authority from the illegitimate
extremes of authoritarianism and permissiveness. Kristol’s insight here echoes
empirical conclusions from scientific child psychology, which has found that,
ironically, authoritarianism (“do as I say because I said so”) and
permissiveness (“do whatever you want”) have similarly ill effects—training
children to be irresponsible and incompetent—whereas the consistent exertion of
legitimate authority (“here’s the right thing to do, here’s why, let’s discuss it
openly and come to a mutual understanding about it”) is the surest formula for
successful child rearing.5
Kristol
also makes the point that authority and liberty are inextricably linked, indeed
that liberty is not possible without a context of legitimate and predictable
authority. For me, this is among the most important points in his chapter,
because it is so little understood or appreciated by much of the educational
community. It is the reason that some of us still have our students read Emile
Durkheim, whose theory elegantly explicated the reasons why, as Kristol writes,
“In the case of authority, power is not experienced as coercive because it is infused,
however dimly, with a moral intention which corresponds to the moral sentiments
and moral ideals of those who are subject to this power.” To the extent that
education is, as Kristol terms it, an “exercise in legitimate authority,” an
offering of moral guidance for developing minds, it is a force for both
personal freedom and character building.
The
future directions pointed to by the authors in this book are based upon what we
have learned from the past. Efforts at character education generally are
well-intended, almost by definition, but good intentions have not always
prevented them from being misguided. In my own travel, I have seen many
mistakes by educators who sincerely want children to acquire virtue and moral
understanding. I have seen skindeep programs that ask students to do nothing
more than recite virtuous words such as honesty, temperance, and respect, and the
words do nothing more than pass in one ear and out the other. I also have seen
adults promoting the very behaviors that they are warning children against. Much
like Sommers, I have heard teachers suggesting to students that it is all right
to cheat on tests that seem meaningless. I have observed adults who counsel
underage minors about alcohol abuse by telling them to stay within a
one-drink-per-hour limit. I have seen teachers look the other way when students
treat one another harshly or unfairly. Such half-hearted messages mock
character education. Children will neglect ideas that adults present
superficially or ambivalently, and are brilliant at picking up subtexts. They
love to explore the half-forbidden.
Any
instruction that begins “I’d rather not have you do this, but if you are going
to anyway, be sure to . . .” is an irresistible invitation to give it a
full-throttle try. The only way to dissuade a child from harmful behavior is
through guidance that the child understands and takes seriously. The only way
to stop cheating is to tell children that it’s wrong, to explain why (it’s
unfair, it’s untrustworthy), and to enforce the sanctions rigorously. The only
alcohol and drug abuse programs that work—that result in less rather than more
risky behavior—are programs that stress avoidance of these dangerous
substances. But conveying don’ts to children can be only a small part of a
successful character education program. Character education must have a
positive side, a call to serve others and to dedicate oneself to a higher
purpose. In the long run, it is a sense of inspiration that sustains good
character. Commitment to a noble purpose can make learned prohibitions
unnecessary. As they say in sports, the best defense is a good offense.
Charitable
work is one way to introduce students to a larger purpose. Research has found
that community service programs, especially when combined with reflection about
the moral and personal significance of serving others, are powerful inducers of
moral growth.6 Spiritual beliefs, too, offer children positive intimations of
transcendent purposes. Another transcendent purpose is the love of country and
selfless dedication to it. In the case of a country that stands as a beacon of
democracy and freedom, this is a noble sentiment. The common word for this
sense of dedication is patriotism, a word
that in recent times has not been welcome in many educational settings; yet
now, when decent societies are called on to combat the evils of international
terror, patriotism of the loftiest sort must resume its rightful place as a
noble source of inspiration for our young. In order to wholly fulfill their
character education missions, schools must open themselves to such sources of
inspiration, becoming places where all students can discover their own moral
callings and noble purposes.
1.
Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986).
2. R.
Shweder, Thinking through Cultures: Expeditions in Cultural Psychology (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1991).
3. Some
key ideas that we wish to pass down to children require an appreciation of
their religious roots in order to fully understand their moral significance.
The work ethic comes to mind as one such notion. Without knowing the
religiously inspired concept of calling (or,
similarly, the classic root of the word vocation), work
can be seen as simply a convention or a nuisance that is too often necessary. I
have heard not only disgruntled workers but also distinguished social
scientists portray work in this way. For the work ethic to be an inspiring
invocation rather than a oppressive injunction, it is important to convey to
youngsters its origins in the belief that one should use one’s occupation to
serve God and, by extension, one’s fellow humans.
4. Ryan
K. and D. Purpel, Moral Education: It Comes with the Territory (New York:
Basic Books, 1977).
5. W.
Damon, The Moral Child (New York: Free Press,
1990); W. Damon, ed. Handbook of Child
Psychology, 5th ed., vol. 1–4 (New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1998).
6. M.
Yates and J. Youniss. The Roots of Civic Identity
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
==============================
Arthur J.
Schwartz
Although
there remain a few skirmishes here and there, the reports from the front lines are
decisive: the battle over the question “Whose values?” has ended. For almost
two decades this culture war has raged on, pitting a platoon of character
educators, parents, and citizens against those (in schools and out) who are
either highly suspicious or skeptical of the character education agenda. In the
end, the primary stakeholders in our schools answered this thorny question for
themselves: local educators, parents, and civic leaders came together in
communities as diverse as Chattanooga and Chicago to reflect upon, identify,
and affirm a set of core values. Even a cursory look at these lists reveals
that moral principles such as honesty, compassion, and respect are the sorts of
attributes that parents want their children to learn in school, practice every
day, and cherish forever. With remarkable clarity and unity, schools and
communities across the United States have put the “Whose values?” question
behind them.
Today the
debate has shifted to an equally thorny question: “How should educators
transmit these core values to our children?” I use the idea of “transmission” purposefully,
recognizing that the term has little contemporary
currency, and for many conjures an extrinsic, cold approach to learning that
deflates the agency of the student in the learning process. I disagree with
this conception of the term “transmission” and I am going to make the case in
this chapter that transmitting moral knowledge and ideals is essential for the
moral health of our American society.
My sense
is that we no longer use the term “transmission” because some fear it will lead
us down a slippery slope to that most villainous of educational terms:
indoctrination. Indeed, from Lawrence Kohlberg’s seminal article
“Indoctrination Versus Relativity in Value Education” in 1971 to Alfie Kohn’s
writings throughout the 1990s, scholars and progressive educators have worried
that the real agenda of character education is to indoctrinate our children.1 For
example, in his 1997 Phi Delta Kappan article,
Kohn writes:
Let me
get straight to the point. What goes by the name of character education
nowadays is, for the most part, a collection of exhortations and extrinsic
inducements designed to make children work harder and do what they’re told.
Even when other values are promoted—caring or fairness, say—the preferred
method of instruction is tantamount to indoctrination. (429,
emphasis added).2
Kohn is
not alone in his sentiment. I do not believe I use hyperbole when I suggest
that there remains a significant group of progressive educators and scholars
who continue to fear that should the grip of character education ever take firm
hold in our schools, our next generation of children will become blindly
obedient to authority, patriotic to a fault—and worst of all—pious and
religious.3
In order
to prevent our schools from taking that perilously short stroll from
transmitting values to indoctrinating students, progressive educators suggest
that sovereign moral autonomy ought to be the endpoint of a moral education.
Teachers should encourage young people to “author” their own moral
constitutions. As Mark Tappan and Lynn Brown write: “In a very real sense
students in a character education program are simply not encouraged to learn
anything from their own moral experience, because such a program denies
students any real moral authority in their own lives.”4 In contrast
to the perceived dogmatism of character education, Tappan and Brown suggest
that teachers ought to provide opportunities for students to reflect upon and
tell their own moral stories (through poems, essays, plays, videos, and so on).
By doing so teachers would be helping their students to “resist and overcome social
and cultural repression” as well as to develop morally. Tappan and Brown
concede that this emphasis and focus is rare in schools, but argue that it
“would be even more difficult, if not impossible, to attain in an educational
setting where all students are indoctrinated into a
fixed set of traditional values, virtues, and rules of conduct”5 (p. 199,
emphasis added).
Putting
aside the inflammatory rhetoric of personal liberation, I glean from the
writings of progressive educators that students should be honest and caring only when
these values constitute their moral identity.
This
conception of moral identity focuses primarily on the authenticity of moral
feelings and self-expression (“what feels good is good”). In addition, these
educators repeatedly assert that something is terribly, terribly wrong if a
student is honest or caring because these are the values that his or her
parent, teacher, mentor, rabbi, or minister think important. The transmission
of values from one generation to the next is dismissed by progressive educators
as traditional or hegemonic or patriarchal in nature. In short, the moral
umbilical cord must be severed cleanly and completely. Mikhael Bakhtin, a
favorite theorist for many educational progressives, sums up this point of view
when he writes: “[O]ne’s own voice, although born of another or dynamically
stimulated by another, will sooner or later begin to liberate itself
from the authority of the other discourses” (emphasis added).6
As
Alasdair MacIntyre would put it, this strident emphasis on attaining moral
autonomy, liberation, and transformation (at all costs) is a “grave, cultural
loss.”7 It seems odd to me that to gain autonomy or to “own” your moral voice
means having to liberate yourself from the sources of your core values—parents,
mentors, religion, or mediating institutions such as Scouting and sports. Even
John Dewey, whose philosophy of education remains an inspiration and ideal for
many contemporary progressive educators, understood the need for transmission of
values. In his classic book Democracy and Education Dewey writes:
“Society not only continues to exist by transmission,
by communication, but it may fairly be said to exist in transmission”
(emphasis added).8 As Dewey suggests, the
purpose of this chapter is to explore how vitally important it has been for
each generation to transmit its moral wisdom to the next generation.
Below I
argue that parents, teachers, and schools transmit core values to their
children and students in a myriad of creative ways and contexts, and that this
traditional form of character education often “sticks to the bones” of our
children and young people whereas more progressive strategies may miss the
mark. More specifically, I consider two classical forms of a character
education that require a process of moral transmission. First, I examine how
parents and educators transmit values to their young by using and reinforcing a
set of maxims and wise sayings that have motivational and moral significance.
Second, I examine how educators transmit the values of honesty, trust, and
integrity to older students through school-based honor codes. My purpose in examining
these two traditional forms of moral education is to shed some light on their
saliency and effectiveness in transmitting core values and ideals. I also
explore how teaching maxims to children and implementing an honor code in high
schools does or does not constitute a form of moral indoctrination. Finally, I
anticipate and confront the question that I suspect concerns all progressive
and character educators: Does transmitting moral maxims and the concept of
honor to our young inhibit or impede their ability to develop their own sense
of moral autonomy?
For the
past several years I have asked literally hundreds of people of all ages to
share with me a maxim or “wise saying” that has been passed on to them. For
example, my best friend told me that as he grew up his father said to him
repeatedly “A job worth doing is a job worth doing well.” To this day, my
friend still hears the voice of his dad as he approaches an important project.
Indeed, while I wrote this chapter my twelve-year-old son, Tyler, told me about
a maxim that he learned while talking to his friend, Chris. They were
discussing how hard it would be for anyone to break the school record for the
mile run. Chris turned to Tyler and said, “Maybe so, but winners never quit,
and quitters never win.” Not surprisingly, Chris told Tyler that his soccer coach
uses that saying all the time.
I define
a maxim as a concise formulation of a fundamental principle or rule of conduct.
Scholars have often commented that the appeal of these wise sayings owes much
to their compact, memorable nature as well as to their usefulness and
timelessness. Although some maxims contain a pronounced moral purpose (“You are
only as good as your word”), other maxims clearly do not (“Absence makes the
heart grow fonder”). My own research focuses on how parents, family members, and
teachers transmit wise sayings to children that have (potentially at least)
moral and motivational power.
Maxims
constitute civilization’s “memory bank.” Humanity has preserved these wise
sayings because they encapsulate a fundamental principle that transcends the
conventions of a particular culture or society. The frozen word order and
archaic lexicon of many maxims (“Do unto others as you would have them do unto
you”) also mark their timeliness and sense of moral authority, which extend
beyond the speaker. Indeed, maxims uncover the voice of a second party—the commanding
voice of one’s elders, sages, or sacred ancestors. Consequently, whether maxims
are seen as embodying universal truths or the norms of a society, they
undeniably distill expressions of wisdom, or what Meider and colleagues call
“apparent truths that have common currency” within a particular culture or
society.9
Young
people usually encounter a maxim by hearing it from another person—often a
parent, relative, or teacher—within a specific social situation. In most cases,
the person speaking or transmitting the maxim is attempting to exhort,
persuade, inspire, offer caution, or to make a point. How many of us, during
childhood, have heard our mothers say to us and our squawking siblings, “Two
wrongs do not make a right”? As young people, we discovered the meaning of this
exhortation by our mothers’ repeated use of the maxim. It is very likely that
our mothers neither intentionally explained the meaning of the maxim, nor told
us how they learned it, nor why it was so meaningful to them. Although the use
of the maxim occurred mostly within the context of sibling conflict (“He
hitmefirst!”), we eventually extended the meaning and use of this particular
maxim to situations that had nothing to do with sibling rivalry. Today, we may
even use the maxim in exactly the same context as our mothers did, now with our
own children and grandchildren.
A growing
body of research indicates, interestingly, that some cultures emphasize the
“proverb tradition” more than others. Strong evidence demonstrates that
proverbs within the African-American culture have a long and distinguished
history as important “cultural keepsakes.” Rarely taught to children in any
formal context, these nuggets of truth are commonly discovered by the young
while interacting with family and elders. In Prhalad’s splendid book, African-American
Proverbs in Context, he recalls how he came to
appreciate the power of this linguistic form:
I fell in
love with proverbs at an early age. I began collecting sayings from calendars
and asking older people what they meant by some of the things that they said .
. . [W]hen I was taken on walks through the woods and shown the beauty and
mystery of plants, I might be told a proverb as a part of that experience. Or a
story might be told about an enslaved ancestor who performed an incredible
feat, with a proverb accompanying the narrative.10
Prhalad
contends that adult-child interactions in general, and the inhome setting in
particular, are the most fertile contexts for proverb and maxim use within the
African-American community. Analyzing data from a number of sources, he
concludes, “[W]hen informants are asked where they learned the proverbs that
they use, most of their examples involve a parent using the proverb to them.”
Much of
Prhalad’s fieldwork focuses on individuals he calls “proverb masters.” His
research indicates that these individuals share several characteristics: (1)
they usually grew up in a home where there was a “proverb master,” often an older
relative such as a grandmother, from whom they learned to interpret and apply
proverbs; (2) they tend to have been and remain very emotionally connected with
that person; and (3) they usually assume the position of bearer and active
guardian of the African-American cultural tradition. Significantly, Prhalad
posits that these men and women begin their “apprenticeship” early in life, imitating
the proverbs of their parents and grandparents, and then sharing their wise
sayings with other children on the playground.
Prhalad
also documents how children often hear and learn particular maxims and wise
sayings from their teachers. For example, Prhalad acquaints us with Mrs.
Dorothy Bishop, who teaches at Golden Gate Elementary School in Oakland,
California. During his fieldwork at the school, Prhalad was astonished at the
number of times that Mrs. Bishop used different proverbs to motivate her
students. In addition, anecdotal evidence indicates that teachers frequently
use maxims in their classrooms as devices to inspire (“Nothing ventured,
nothing gained”), to caution (“What goes around comes around”), or to redirect
the behavior of their students (“If you cannot saying something nice, say
nothing”). In his recent memoir Teachers of My Youth, the
distinguished philosopher of education, Israel Scheffler, reflects on the value
one of his teachers placed on reciting and memorizing particular biblical
passages:
In
memorizing and reciting, we had used not only our eyes and ears but our vocal
cords, not only our receptive apparatus but also our motor equipment—getting
the feel of producing the words. [I]n becoming ours, these words would
occasionally arise in our minds spontaneously; they would appear and sing
freely, without waiting for an invitation. They
still visit me to this day and I am grateful to Mr. Leideker for having such a
stress on what is now often scorned as an outmoded pedagogical procedure (emphasis
added).11
Clearly,
reciting a maxim aloud repeatedly or writing it in a copybook are two
time-honored memorization strategies used by generations of elders and
teachers. Whether they are Prhalad’s proverb masters or teachers such as Mr.
Leideker, elders have historically borne the responsibility to transmit these
words of wisdom to their young.
Let me
state my point emphatically: While teachers should
strive to have their students invest personal meaning in a wise saying, relying
solely on affective or associative attachment to a set of maxims or proverbs without
memorization strategies is ill-advised and shortsighted. Drill and
practice are essential components of a successful performance, whether it is on
the athletic field, in the concert hall, or in a civic-minded and ethical life.
If isolated from other strategies that guide students to connect what they are
memorizing to their own experiences, drill does kill.
Memory
research confirms that information is more quickly and firmly embedded in
memory when it is tied to meaningful experience, emotion, and personal
motivation. However, I suggest that character educators should employ in their
schools and classrooms the traditional method of challenging their students to
memorize maxims and to develop creative strategies that help their students
connect a particular maxim to their own experiences, feelings, and motivations.
Let’s
assume a high school teacher wants her children to learn the Christopher
Brothers-inspired proverb, “It is better to light a single candle than to curse
the darkness.” Utilizing a number of strategies, she might guide her students
to connect the meaning of the proverb to their own ethical experiences and
moral identities. When have they stood up to confront a wrong or an injustice
instead of simply turning the other way? She might also explain why this
proverb is important to her (perhaps why she is a member of Amnesty
International), or she might offer examples of historical and contemporary
moral exemplars who have embodied the proverb (such as Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn
or Mother Teresa). Finally, she should develop an assessment tool to determine whether
her students have developed the ability to grasp the meaning and importance of
the proverb. Her assessment, however, should also include whether her students
have successfully memorized the proverb.
Why is
memorization of a maxim an important teaching outcome? I think E. D. Hirsch and
his colleagues had it just right when they argued that there exists a cluster
of maxims and proverbs that “every American needs to know.”12 Just as
stakeholders debated and eventually agreed on which core values should serve as
guideposts for their character education programs, my own view is that local
communities and educators should discern which maxims are most critical or
important for children to learn.13 The point
I want to underscore is that educators and elders have a historical
responsibility to intentionally transmit a set of cultural keepsakes to our
young. Although approaches and curricula have changed dramatically, for several
millennia elders have provided their young with an apprenticeship into
responsible adulthood. The challenge for us today is to weave a character
education that emphasizes personal meaning as well as the time-honored method
of memorizing maxims that have moral and motivational power.
Considerable
anecdotal evidence suggests that today educators are struggling to find
effective ways to transmit and inculcate a set of core values beyond the
elementary school years. Clearly, most character education programs that
emphasize core values are designed for K-6 students. By the time students enter
high school, what we commonly call character education has often been conflated
or watered down to mean nothing more than the prevention of harmful behaviors:
alcohol and drug prevention, violence prevention, pregnancy prevention. These prevention
programs focus largely on what high school students should avoid and rarely (if
at all) do these initiatives reinforce or emphasize the constellation of core
values that served as ethical touchstones during the elementary school years.
There are some glaring exceptions to this rule. In this chapter, I would like
to focus on the few private high schools in the United States that have an
honor code system that forms the moral center from which all other activities
related to character education spiral out. Although none of these schools
advertise or even suggest that their honor code serves as a panacea or
prophylactic to the array of harmful behaviors highlighted above, they proudly
defend their honor code system as one of the primary pedagogical vehicles by
which school officials, older students, parents, and alumni transmit the
institution’s core values to new and returning students.
At the
postsecondary level, and largely through the efforts of the Center for Academic
Integrity, a growing number of colleges and universities are initiating
campus-wide programs to identify a set of fundamental values that underpin the
standards of academic integrity. These core values include honesty, trust,
respect, fairness, and responsibility. Recently, the Center has disseminated
data collected by Donald McCabe and his colleagues showing that college
campuses with academic honor codes do indeed have lower levels of student
dishonesty than schools with other sorts of initiatives designed to uphold the
importance of academic integrity.14 Taken
together, the anecdotal and empirical evidence is compelling and clear: honor
codes are effective in transmitting a set of core values to students. The
question I explore below is why.
What is
an honor code? In high school settings only, at the most simplistic level, a
school’s honor code is nothing but a cluster of words that explain a school’s
policy related to honest and dishonest conduct. In most schools this policy is
limited to academic work, while some honor codes may extend to all domains of
personal and social responsibility. Whether a high school student reads about
the code in the school handbook, learns about it during the admission or
orientation process, or hears about it from faculty or fellow students, for
most new students the honor code is likely to represent (at least in the
beginning) nothing more than an official injunction against lying, stealing, or
cheating related to academic work. Most administrators and faculty involved in
honor education agree that personal interactions and experiences with the
concept of honor is almost always required before new students begin to feel a
sense of personal ownership related to the school’s honor code.
There are
several discrete approaches by which an honor code system is transmitted to
students. For example, on some campuses a school’s honor code has a strong
tradition or history, and this story is transmitted to new students in a wide
variety of ways—from historical narratives in the student handbook and school
website to personal narratives during convocation where an administrator,
faculty member, current student, or recent alumnus exhorts the students to
uphold the “[fill in school’s name] honor system.” Almost all schools (both
secondary and postsecondary) hold a ceremony or honor convocation at the beginning
of the academic year where the school formally asks each student to take an
oath (either in writing or verbally) stating that he or she will live by the
fundamental values embodied in the honor system. When a strong honor system is
in place, the honor code is reinforced and upheld by faculty members throughout
the academic year.
Perhaps
most important are the interactions of newer students with student leaders, who
serve as the strongest defenders and advocates for the honor system. In many
cases, these student leaders have the primary responsibility to educate the
entire student body about the honor code system. Educators often remark that
the depth of commitment that these students express and model in relation to
the values of the honor code is critical in helping other students to
understand that the honor system is not a cold structure but a “felt ideal.”
Perhaps the motto of the cadets who serve on the honor code committee at West Point
says it all: “The more we educate, the less we investigate.”
Finally,
there are some students who come before the honor board or council itself,
having been accused or found in violation of the honor system. In the
publication A Handbook for Developing and Sustaining Honor
Codes by David Gould (which focuses solely on honor systems at the high school
level), a student from Saint Andrew’s High School, Boca Raton, Florida, offers
his own unique perspective on what is learned when a student appears before a
school’s honor council:
The
experience of being brought before the honor board is far more powerful than
that of being brought before the dean of students, for example. Here, a student
must not only face his or her bad decisions, but he or she must also do so in
front of a panel of peers. Having never come before the Saint Andrew’s honor
board, I do not know the range of feelings that might surface during a hearing,
but as a member of the honor board, I can
infer from students brought before the board that shame might be a predominant
emotion. A group of peers, some of whom might be in this student’s classes,
have said that what he or she did was wrong and his or her actions did not meet
the expectations of the student body. The power of such an experience should
not be underestimated. I have known or heard of several students who, as ninth
or tenth graders, were brought before the honor board and who subsequentlybecome
so dedicated to honor that, as eleventh or twelfth graders, they were chosen by
faculty and students to join the honor board (emphasis added).15
The
student’s use of the term “shame” is critical here. The concept of honor, and
how the ideal of honor is transmitted, cannot be fully understood or
operationalized unless we understand the relationship between honor and shame.
Damon has written that shame is a moral emotion that can form and shape our
hearts and minds.16 This sort of shame is not
toxic, certainly not in the way that shame is talked about most of the time in
our contemporary culture. Instead, the avoidance of shame is often a powerful
and positive moral motivator.17
The
Greeks knew this well. Aidos, a term
common to Greek plays and philosophy, denotes sensitivity to and protectiveness
of one’s self image. This moral emotion is not just a bodily sensation such as
fear or anger; instead, aidos is an
intense negative appraisal of the self. The moral emotion of aidos is felt
when an individual believes he or she has committed a wrong.18
Within
the context of classical Greek society, several components needed to be in
place for a person to feel ashamed. First, there needs to be an audience.
Unlike the feelings of guilt or embarrassment, feelings of honor and shame are
inextricably bound up with a respected group of people. The etymology of the
term “honor” clearly illustrates this reciprocal relationship. The term comes
from the Latin honos, meaning
an honor (such as receiving an honorary degree) awarded to someone. Thus, the
concept of honor historically was not something you have, but something given
to you (by those you respect and whose respect you seek). For example, in Richard
II Shakespeare writes, “Mine honor is my life. Take honor from me and my
life is done.” At their fundamental core, the concepts of honor and shame are
bound up with our obligations to others and our concern for the opinion of
others.
Second,
in Greek culture the emotion of shame emerges only when an individual has
fallen short of a moral ideal that establishes what kind of person an
individual is or would like to be. This is an important point to reinforce.
Greek society placed great emphasis on the “excellences of persons” and on
striving to attain such excellence in the right way, at the right time, for the
right reasons. Thus, shame occurs only when an individual has strong desires to
be a particular kind of person—and fails. Perhaps this may explain why a person
of honor does what is right even in the absence of potential sanctions or the
possibility of getting caught.19
Last,
Greek society emphasized education as essential to honor. The elders knew that
educating their young to have right desires was far more important than
legislating laws and sanctions. For the Greeks (as well as for those in
contemporary times), there are three time-tested methods used by educators to
effectively transmit a moral standard of honor against which an individual or
school wishes to be measured: (1) the ideal of honor needs to be clearly
established, reinforced, and defended; (2) fundamental values of honor must be
consistently modeled by teachers and elders; (3) ample opportunities for the
young to practice (and eventually habituate) the values linked with the ideal
of honor must be provided.
What is
most important to recognize in terms of moral development theory is that a
person’s attachment to the ideal of honor is both a cognitive and affective
achievement. Aristotle calls this state hexeis, a settled
disposition that is long-lasting and therefore hard to change. That is,
individuals who have internalized the virtues of honor (perhaps student leaders
of the honor system) choose to uphold the honor code not because they fear
being shamed or disgraced by their peers, but because they have acquired a
personal, often emotional and visceral, revulsion against dishonest actions.
This may help us better to understand the meaning of the phrase “for the love
of honor.” Even individuals who are less emotionally attached to the concept of
honor have a set of sturdy cognitive hooks to grab. They may realize that they
can never be proud of anything they got by cheating, or they may reason that
cheating is unfair to all people, or perhaps they comprehend that a person who
cheats in school now will find it easier to cheat in other situations later in
life, perhaps even in one’s closest personal relationships. 20
I am
aware that the portrait I have painted of Greek moral culture and the
significance of honor and shame in that society is a historical ideal, and must
be viewed against today’s society, youth culture, and educational priorities.
Indeed, there are real questions (even compelling statistics) about whether
kids can “police” themselves in a contemporary culture where the dominant
student code appears to be “thou shall not judge others.” Data also suggest
that students cheat to please their parents and to maintain (at all costs) a
successful image. There is considerable data to suggest that teachers simply
look the other way. All these factors challenge administrators, teachers, and
students committed to implementing and sustaining an honor system at their
schools.21
Let me
emphasize that even when educators recognize that there has never been a honor
system that works perfectly all the time (or always for the right reasons),
instituting an honor code system in high schools and colleges is anything but a
form of indoctrination. An honor system impels, prompts, and motivates students
to reflect on what it means to live in a community that affirms and defends a
set of ideals related to honor and integrity. In this way, high schools that
implement and reinforce an honor system are laboratories of moral learning, and
student fidelity to the school’s honor code is a powerful voice that counters
society’s prevailing perception that all of us are unencumbered, morally free
agents. The moment students begin to care about upholding the honor system,
they can no longer make whatever decisions they want. They cannot be moved by
mere impulse or inclination.
The
fundamental values that constitute the ideal of honor not only limit their
freedom but guide their moral actions. Establishing and sustaining an honor
code system is a powerful way to transmit a set of values and ideals that
extend beyond a shallow and brutish conception of ethical behavior summed up
as, “You stay out of my business and I will stay out of yours.”
This
chapter had three objectives. First, I sought to examine how parents, teachers,
and schools use maxims to transmit core values to young children and how honor
codes transmit the values of honor to highschool students. Second, I wanted to
explore whether these traditional character education approaches constituted a
form of moral indoctrination. Last, I hoped to shed some light on whether the
use of maxims and honor systems inhibits or impedes a young person’s ability to
develop his or her own moral autonomy.
We need
only look at Nazi Germany or Mao’s China to agree with progressive educators
that indoctrination has reared its ugly head in the twentieth century.
Specifically, scholars have determined that indoctrination occurs in schools
and classrooms when: (1) the intention of a teacher or school is to make
students believe in something despite the evidence; (2) the teaching methods
are coercive or clearly inappropriate; (3) the content consists of prescribed
doctrines and ideologies and everything else is strictly prohibited; and (4)
the consequence of the education results in a closed, intolerant mind.22
My position
is that the use of maxims and honor codes in our schools doesn’t even come
close to the threshold of indoctrination. I urge all progressive educators to
stop using the term “indoctrination” when describing the objectives of
character education. The term is an affront to the thousands of people—men and
women, liberal and conservative, of all ethnicities and religions—who care
deeply that American society, specifically our young people, may be
experiencing moral vertigo. Instead, these educators should feel free to use
the term “transmission.”
Character
educators desperately want to transmit core values to our students. We are
trying our best to pass on a substantial ethical endowment to our children.
Even John Dewey emphasizes that this is the solemn responsibility of each
generation. He writes:
The
things in civilization we most prize are not of ourselves. They exist by grace
of the doings and sufferings of the continuous human community in which we are
a link. Ours is the responsibility of conserving, transmitting, rectifying and
expanding the heritage of values we have received that those
who come after us may receive it more solid and secure, more widely accessible
and more generously shared than we have received it (emphasis added).23
We must
recognize, however, that there are real differences between progressive and
character educators on what is meant by the term “moral autonomy.” Among
character educators, there is a prevailing sentiment that progressive educators
want to encourage every young person to metaphorically climb his or her own Mt.
Sinai and return with tablets on which he or she has written what is good and
what is moral for him or her alone. Moreover, the authors of these personalized
tablets should feel free to amend them at any time, for any reason.
Progressive
educators, on the other hand, perceive that character educators want to impose
a moral education that begins and ends with the Ten Commandments. Here is the
fundamental fault line today—a battle between David (the radically emancipated
self) and Goliath (the wisdom of the past).
Where can
we begin to bridge this gap? It might be helpful, in a spirit of humility, to
initiate a dialogue that explores more deeply Dewey’s call to
conserve, transmit, rectify and expand the heritage of values. Many of
us would agree that character educators seem to emphasize—both in rhetoric and
practice—the strategies of conserving and transmitting, whereas progressive
educators largely seek to rectify and expand our common constellation of
values. Would it also be interesting to listen to character educators describe
how they make sense of Dewey’s call to expand and rectify our heritage of
values, and learn the ways in which progressive educators do try to conserve
and transmit values? How might a discussion on child development theories draw
us closer to consensus on some of these essential questions? Would it be
helpful to address the perception of progressive educators that character
education seeks to emphasize a small cluster of core values such as obedience, punctuality,
regularity, silence, and industry?24 These are
all critical questions.
Foremost,
we should all strive to be more attentive to the terms we use to describe the
moral development. For example, using the term “integration” instead of “autonomy” or
“internalization” might better enable us to understand that moral development
includes integrating motivational and emotional systems with a set of moral
values and ideals transmitted to us. “Integration” also suggests that this
process of moral development is fragile, ongoing, and demands constant
attention, instead of something that is sudden and dramatic (such as Paul’s
conversion experience on the road to Damascus). Moreover, the term suggests sensitivity
to how unlikely it is that any of us are fully sovereign, radically autonomous
moral beings. As Gus Blasi writes: “It is possible that the integration
of moral understanding and motivation is not achieved at approximately
the same age for the whole body of moral norms and virtues, but must be worked
out separately for different issues” (emphasis added).25 In other
words, my best friend will always hear his father’s voice telling him that “a
job worth doing is a job worth doing well.” Why is this voice any less authentic
than his own?
There is
also much work ahead for the field of character education. I agree with
progressive educators that the language of moral energy and moral feeling, or
what Carol Gilligan calls “felt knowledge,” is too often absent from character
education literature and programs.26 Young people
have a strong desire to know the world rather than simply get along with it.
Our emotions are a critical component of the moral life, and without them our
moral lives would be flat and empty. None of us are pure Kantians who live by
duty alone. Emotions anchor our moral lives, and to sever this connection is to
weaken the motivational springs of moral behavior. As I have said above,
whether it is the use of maxims or upholding an honor code, our moral actions
often flow from our attachment, commitment, and desire to a set of moral
ideals. Character educators must find a way to more robustly integrate the fuel
of emotion as a fundamental component of their programs and activities.
Here is
where my own favorite maxim might help to bring these two educational
perspectives together. The philosopher Charles Taylor once suggested that strong
convictions require strong sources.27 In other words,
our convictions are forged within the crucible of personal experience and from
the wisdom transmitted to us by family members, our religious tradition, our
school traditions, and life lessons learned from a significant teacher or
mentor. Unfortunately, these later sources of wisdom are too frequently
neglected or overlooked, even in character education programs. Thus, the
challenge for the next generation of character educators is to develop a pedagogy
that inspires young people to integrate these sources of wisdom with their own
moral experiences.
1. See
Lawrence Kohlberg, “Indoctrination versus Relativity in Value Education,” Zygonu (1971):
285–310.
2. Alfie
Kohn, “How Not to Discuss Character Education,” Phi Delta Kappan (1997):
429–39.
3. See
Michael Apple and James Beane, eds., Democratic Schools (Alexandria,
Va.: Association for Supervision and Curriculum Development, 1995); James
Beane, Affect in the Curriculum (New York: Teachers College
Press, 1990); Rheta DeVries and Betty Zan, Moral Classrooms, Moral
Children: Creating a Constructivist Atmosphere in Early Education (New
York: Teachers College Press, 1994); Deborah Meier, The Power of Their Ideas (Boston:
Beacon Press, 1995); George Noblit and Van O. Dempsey, The Social
Construction of Virtue: The Moral Life of Schools (New York: State University
of New York Press, 1996); David Purpel, The Moral and Spiritual
Crisis in Education (New York: Bergin &
Garvey, 1989); Gregory Smith, Public Schools That Work:
Creating Community (New York: Routledge,
1993).
4. Mark
Tappan and Lynn Mikel Brown, “Stories Told and Lessons Learned: Toward a
Narrative Approach to Moral Development and Moral Education,” Harvard Educational
Review 59:2 (1989): 182–205.
5. Ibid.,
199.
6. See
Mikhael Bakhtin. The Dialogic Imagination.C.
Emerson and M. Holquist, trans. (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1981): 348.
7.
Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (South
Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981).
8. John Dewey,
Democracy and Education (New York: Macmillan
Publishing, 1916): 4.
9. See S.
Meider, S. A. Kingsbury, and K. B. Harder, A Dictionary of American Proverbs
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).
10. Anand
Prhalad, African-American Proverbs in Context (Jackson: University Press of
Mississippi, 1996): 122.
11.
Israel Scheffler, Teachers of My Youth: An American Jewish
Experience (Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1995): 98.
12. E. D.
Hirsch, J. Kett, and J. Trefil, The Dictionary of Cultural
Literacy: What Every American Needs to Know (New York: Dell Publishing,
1998).
13. With
support from the John Templeton Foundation, a number of communities and schools
have begun to help their students identify a set of core maxims. For example, under
the leadership of Donald Biggs and Robert Colesante, high school and elementary
students in Albany, New York, recently interviewed adults and mentors in Albany
to learn which maxims and wise sayings are used in the African-American
community to transmit the importance of working hard and setting goals. See
Robert Colesante and Donald Biggs, The Fifth Albany Institute
for Urban Youth Leadership Development: Teaching and Advocating for the Work
Ethic. Final report to the John Templeton Foundation, 2000.
14. See Donald
McCabe and Patrick Drinan, “Towards a Culture of Academic Integrity,” The
Chronicle of Higher Education (October 15, 1999): B7.
15. David
Gould, A Handbook for Developing and Sustaining Honor Codes (Atlanta:
Council for Spiritual and Ethical Education, 1999): 55.
16.
William Damon, The Moral Child (New York: Free Press,
1988).
17. The
concepts of honor and shame can only be understood within their historical context.
In addition, honor and shame have historically meant something quite different for
men and women. For a feminist analysis of shame, see Barbara Eurich-Roscoe and Hendrika
Kemp, Femininity and Shame: Women, Men, and Giving Voice to the Feminine (New
York: University Press of America, 1997).
18. I
amindebted to Douglas Cairns’s magisterial examination of the aidos concept. See
Douglas Cairns, Aidos: The Psychology and Ethics of Honour
and Shame in Ancient Greek Literature (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1993).
19. This
perspective is frequently advanced by scholars in response to Plato’s question about
the Ring of Gyges: Why would anyone not use the ring (which made the wearer
invisible) to “take what he wanted from the market without fear?”
20. See
Thomas Lickona, Educating for Character: How Our Schools Can
Teach Respect and Responsibility (New York: Bantam Books,
1991): 77.
21. See
Kevin Bushweller, “Generation of Cheaters,” The American School Board Journal
(April 1999): 24–32.
22. I. A.
Snook, Indoctrination and Education (London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul, 1972).
23. John
Dewey, A Common Faith (New Haven, Conn.: Yale
University Press, 1934): 87.
24. It is
important to recognize that for over a century U.S. public schools have been
influenced by a dominant perspective of schooling that has de-emphasized the moral
functions of feeling and desire. This position was perhaps most forcefully
delineated by William T. Harris, the first United States commissioner of
education. In an influential 1888 report of the Committee in Moral Education of
the National Council of Education he listed the virtues above as essential to
the moral training of students. See John Elias, Moral Education: Secular
and Religious (Malabar, Fla.: Robert E. Krieger Publishing
Company, 1989): 24.
25.
Augusto Blasi, “Moral Understanding and Moral Personality: The Process of Moral
Integration.” In W. M. Kurtines and J. L. Lewirtz, eds., Moral
Development: An Introduction (Boston: Allyn & Bacon,
1996): 238.
26. Carol
Gilligan, “Adolescent Development Reconsidered,” In Approaches to Moral
Education, Andrew Garrod, ed. (New York: Teachers College Press, 1993): 104.
27.
Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of Modern
Identity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1989).
==============================
Christina
Hoff Sommers
Romanticism
is always valuable as a protest. But another sort of trouble starts when
romantics themselves get into positions of authority and demand that children
shall scamper around being ‘creative’ and spontaneously ‘discovering’ what it
has taken civilized man centuries to understand.1
—Professor
Richard Peters, Philosopher of Education, Oxford
Hannah Arendt
is said to have remarked that every year civilization is invaded by the
millions of tiny barbarians: they are called children. All cultures try to
civilize the invaders by educating them and inculcating a sense of right and
wrong. Ours, however, may be the first to question the propriety of doing so.
What happens when democratic societies deprive children of the moral knowledge
that took civilized man centuries to understand? What happens when educators
celebrate children’s creativity and innate goodness but abandon the ancestral responsibility
to discipline, train, and civilize them? Unfortunately, we know the answer: we
are just emerging from a thirty-year laissez-aller experiment in moral
deregulation.
In the
fall of 1996, I took part in a televised ethics program billed as a Socratic
dialogue. For an hour, I joined another ethics professor, a history teacher, and
seven high school students in a discussion of moral dilemmas. The program,
“Ethical Choices: Individual Voices,” was shown on public television and is now
circulated to high schools for use in classroom discussions of right and wrong.2 Its
message still troubles me. In one typical exchange, the moderator, Stanford law
professor Kim Taylor-Thompson, posed this dilemma to the students. Your teacher
has unexpectedly assigned you a five-page paper. You have only a few days to do
it, and you are already overwhelmed with work. Would it be wrong to hand in
someone else’s paper? Two of the students found the suggestion unthinkable and
spoke about responsibility, honor, and principle. “I wouldn’t do it. It is a
matter of integrity,” said Elizabeth. “It’s dishonest,” said Erin. Two others
saw nothing wrong with cheating. Eleventh-grader Joseph flatly said, “If you
have the opportunity, you should use it.” Eric concurred. “I would use the
paper and offer it to my friends.”
I have
taught moral philosophy to college freshmen for more than fifteen years, so I
was not surprised to find students on the PBS program defending cheating. There
are some in every class, playing devil’s advocate with an open admiration for
the devil’s position. That evening, in our PBS Socratic dialogue, I expected at
least to have a professional ally in the other philosophy teacher, who surely
would join me in making the case for honesty. Instead, the professor defected.
He told the students that in this situation, it was the teacher who was immoral
for having given the students such a burdensome assignment and was disappointed
in us for not seeing it his way. “What disturbs me,” he said, “is how accepting
you all seem to be of this assignment . . . to me it’s outrageous from the
point of view of learning to force you to write a paper in this short a time.”
Through
most of the session the professor focused on the hypocrisy of parents,
teachers, and corporations, but had little to say about the moral obligations
of the students. When we discussed the immorality of shoplifting, he implied
that stores are in the wrong for their pricing policies and he talked about
“corporations deciding on a twelve percent profit margin . . . and perhaps
sweatshops.” The professor was friendly and, to all appearances, well-meaning.
Perhaps his goal was to empower students to question authority and rules. That,
however, is something contemporary adolescents already know how to do. Too
often, we teach students to question principles before they even vaguely
understand them. In this case, the professor advised high school students to
question moral teachings and rules of behavior that are critical to their
wellbeing.
The
professor’s hands-off style has been fashionable in the public schools for
thirty years. It has gone under various names such as values clarification,
situation ethics, and self-esteem guidance. These so-called value-free
approaches to ethics have flourished at a time when many parents fail to give
children basic guidance in right and wrong. The story of why so many children
are being deprived of elementary moral training encompasses three or four
decades of misguided reforms by educators, parents, and judges has yet to be
entirely told. Reduced to its philosophical essentials, it is the story of the
triumph of Jean-Jacques Rousseau
over Aristotle.
Some
2,300 years ago Aristotle laid down what children need: clear guidance on how
to be moral human beings. What Aristotle advocates became the default model for
moral education over the centuries. He shows parents and teachers how to
civilize the invading hordes of child barbarians. It is only recently that many
educators have begun to denigrate his teachings. Aristotle regards children as
wayward, uncivilized, and very much in need of discipline. The early Christian
philosopher, St. Augustine, went further, regarding the child’s refractory
nature as a manifestation of the original sin committed by Adam and Eve when they
rebelled against the dictates of God. Each philosopher, in his way, regards
perversity as a universal feature of human nature. Aristotle compares moral
education to physical training. Just as we become strong and skillful by doing
things that require strength and skill, so, he says, do we become good by
practicing goodness. Ethical education, as he understands it, is training in
emotional control and disciplined behavior. Habituation to right behavior comes
before an appreciation or understanding of why we should be good. He advocated
first socializing children by inculcating habits of decency, using suitable
punishments and rewards to discipline them to behave well. Eventually they
understand the reasons and advantages of being moral human beings.
Far from
giving priority to the free expression of emotion, Aristotle (and Plato)
teaches that moral development is achieved by educating children to modulate
their emotions. For Aristotle, self-awareness means being aware of and avoiding
behaviors that reason proscribes but emotion dictates. “We must notice the
errors into which we ourselves are liable to fall (because we all have
different tendencies) . . . and then we must drag ourselves in the contrary
direction.”3 Children with good moral habits gain control over the intemperate side
of their natures and grow into free and flourishing human beings.
The moral
virtues . . . are engendered in us neither by nor contrary to nature; we are
constituted by nature to receive them, but their full development is due to
habit . . . . So it is a matter of no little importance what sort of habits we
form from the earliest age—it makes a vast difference, or rather all the
difference in the world.4
Aristotle’s
general principles for raising moral children were unquestioned through most of
Western history; even today his teachings represent common-sense opinion about
child rearing, but in the eighteenth century, the Aristotle’s wisdom was
directly challenged by the theories of the enlightenment philosopher Jean
Jacques Rousseau. Rousseau denies that children are born wayward (originally
sinful), insisting instead that children are, by nature, noble, virtuous beings
who are corrupted by an intrusive socialization. The untutored child is
spontaneously good and graceful. “When I picture to myself a boy of ten or twelve,
healthy, strong and well-built for his age, only pleasant thoughts arise . . .
. I see him bright, eager, vigorous, care-free, completely absorbed in the
present, rejoicing in abounding vitality.”5
According
to Rousseau “the first education should be purely negative. . . . It consists
not in teaching virtue or truth, but in preserving the heart from vice and the
mind from error.”6 He rejects the traditional notion
that moral education in the early stages must habituate the child to virtuous
behavior:
The only
habit a child should be allowed to acquire is to contract none. . . . Prepare
in good time for the reign of freedom and the exercise of his powers, but
allowing his body its natural habits and accustoming him always to be his own
master and follow the dictates of his will as soon as he has a will of his own.7
Contrary
to the received view, Rousseau believes the child’s nature is originally good
and free of sin. As he sees it, a proper education provides the soil for the
flourishing of the child’s inherently good nature, bringing it forth unspoiled
and fully effective. In his view, the goal of moral education is defeated when
an external code is imposed on children. Rousseau is modern in his distrust of
socially ordained morals as well as in his belief that the best education elicits
the child’s own authentic (benevolent) nature. Rousseau emphatically rejects
the Christian doctrine that human beings are innately rebellious and naturally sinful:
Let us
lay it down as an incontestable principle that the first impulses of nature are
always right. There is no original perversity in the human heart.8
Although
Rousseau is against instilling moral habits in a free and noble being, he
allows that the child’s development requires guidance and encouragement to
elicit its own good nature. He urges parents and tutors to put the child’s
“kindly feelings into action.”9
Christian
and classical pagan thinkers are convinced that far more is needed. They insist
that virtue cannot be attained without a directive moral training that
habituates the child to virtuous behavior. Saint Augustine and the orthodox
Christian thinkers are especially pessimistic about the efficacy of putting
kindly feelings into action. According to Augustine, not even the most
disciplined moral education guarantees a virtuous child: education without
divine help (grace) is insufficient. By contrast, not only do Rousseau’s
followers deny the Augustinian doctrine that our natures are originally sinful
and rebellious—they further regard directive moral education as an assault on
the child’s right to develop freely.
There is
much to admire in Rousseau. He argued for humane child rearing at a time when
cruel rigidity was the norm. Though his criticisms of the educational practices
of his day are valid, his own recommendations have simply not proved workable.
It is, perhaps, worth noting that he did not apply his fine theories to his own
life and was altogether irresponsible in dealing with his own children.10 His
theories, too, are marred by inconsistencies. On the one hand, he is firmly
against instilling habits in a child; on the other, he dispenses a lot of sound
Aristotelian advice to parents for habituating their children to the classical
virtues: “Keep your pupil occupied with all the good deeds.”
Despite
his celebration of freedom, even Rousseau would be appalled by the
permissiveness we see so much of today. “The surest way to make your child
unhappy,” he wrote, “is to accustom him to get everything he wants.”11 All the
same, Rousseau parted company with the traditionalists on the crucial question
of human nature. For better or worse, Rousseau’s followers ignored his
Aristotelian side and developed the progressive elements of his educational
philosophy.
Though we
wish to believe him, Rousseau’s rosy picture of the child fails to convince. In
Emile, Rousseau states that although children may do
bad deeds, a child can never be said to be bad “because wrong action depends on
harmful intention and that he will never have.”12 This
flies in the face of common experience. Most parents and teachers will tell you
that children often have harmful intentions. In perhaps the most famous
description of children’s “harmful intentions,” Saint Augustine, in his Confessions,
describes his boyhood pleasure in doing wrong—simply for the joy of flouting
prohibitions. Some parents and teachers might indeed find Augustine’s
description of children’s unruly nature understated and some will find
Golding’s Lord of the Flies an even more telling
description of what children are naturally like than that of Augustine’s wayward
boyhood friends.
Rousseau
powerfully dominates the thinking of the theorists whose influence pervades
modern schools of education. In pedagogy, Rousseau’s views inspired the
progressive movement in education, which turned away from rote teaching and
sought methods to free the child’s creativity. Rousseau’s ideas are also
deployed to discredit the traditional directive style of moral education
associated with Aristotelian ethical theory and Judeo-Christian religion and
practice.
The
directive style of education, denigrated as indoctrination, was cast aside in
the second half of the twentieth century and discontinued as the progressive
style became dominant. By the seventies, character education had been
effectively discredited and virtually abandoned in practice.
In 1970,
Theodore Sizer, then dean of the Harvard School of Education, coedited with his
wife, Nancy, a collection of ethics lectures entitled Moral
Education.13 The preface set the tone by condemning the morality of the Christian
gentleman, the American prairie, the McGuffey
Readers, and the hypocrisy of teachers who tolerate a grading system that is
the “terror of the young.”14 The
Sizers were especially critical of the “crude and philosophically simpleminded
sermonizing tradition” of the nineteenth century. They referred to directive
ethics education in all its guises as the old morality. According to the
Sizers, leading moralists agree that that kind of morality “can and should be scrapped.”
The Sizers favored a new morality that gives primacy to students’ autonomy and
independence. Teachers should never preach or attempt to inculcate virtue;
rather, through their actions, they should demonstrate a fierce commitment to
social justice. In part, that means democratizing the classroom: “Teacher and
children can learn about morality from each other.”15
The
Sizers preached a doctrine already practiced in many schools throughout the
country. Schools were scrapping the old morality in favor of alternatives that
gave primacy to the children’s moral autonomy. Values clarification was popular
in the seventies and its proponents consider it inappropriate for a teacher to
encourage students, however indirectly, to adopt the values of the teacher or
the community. The cardinal sin is to impose values on the student. Instead,
the teacher’s job is to help the students discover their own values. In Readings
in Values Clarification, two of the leaders of the
movement, Sidney Simon and Howard Kirschenbaum, explain what is wrong with
traditional ethics education:
We call
this approach “moralizing,” although it has also been known as inculcation,
imposition, indoctrination, and in its most extreme form, “brainwashing.”16
Lawrence
Kohlberg, a Harvard moral psychologist, developed cognitive moral development,
a second favored approach. Kohlberg shared the Sizers’ low opinion of
traditional morality, referring disdainfully to the “old bags of virtues” that
earlier educators had sought to inculcate.17 Kohlbergian
teachers were more traditional than the proponents of values clarification.
They sought to promote a Kantian awareness of duty and responsibility in
students. Kohlberg was traditional in his opposition to the moral relativism
that many progressive educators found congenial; all the same, Kohlbergians
shared with other progressives a scorn for any form of top-down inculcation of
moral principles.
They too
believed in student-centered teaching, where the teacher acts less as a guide
than as a facilitator of the student’s development. Kohlberg himself later
changed his mind and conceded that his rejection of indoctrinative moral
education had been a mistake.18 His admirable
recantation had little effect. The next fashion in progressive pedagogy,
student-centered learning, was soon to leave the Kohlbergians and the values
clarifiers far behind. By the late eighties, self-esteem education had become
all the rage. Ethics was superseded by attention to the child’s personal sense
of well-being: the school’s primary aim was to teach children to prize their
rights and self-worth. In the old days, teachers asked seventh graders to write
about “The Person I Admire Most.” But in today’s child-centered curriculum,
they ask children to write essays celebrating themselves. In one popular middle
school English text, an assignment called “The Nobel Prize for Being You”
informs students that they are “wonderful” and “amazing” and instructs them to:
Create
two documents in connection with your Nobel Prize. Let the first document be a
nomination letter written by the personwho knows you best. Let the second be
the script for your acceptance speech, which you will give at the annual award
ceremony in Stockholm, Sweden.19
For extra
credit, students can award themselves a trophy “that is especially designed for
you and no one else.”
Through
most of human history, children learned about virtue and honor by hearing or
reading the inspiring stories of great men and women. By the 1990s, this
practice, which many educators regarded as too directive, was giving way to
practices that suggested to students that they were their own best guides in
life. This turn to the autonomous subject as the ultimate moral authority is a
notable consequence of the triumph of the progressive style over traditional
directive methods of education.
It’s hard
to see how the Harvard theorists who urged teachers to jettison the “crude and
philosophically simpleminded sermonizing tradition of the nineteenth century”
could defend the crude egoism that has replaced it. Apart from the philosophical
niceties, there are concrete behavioral consequences. The moral deregulation
that the New England educators required took hold in the very decades that saw
a rise in conduct disorders among children in the nation’s schools. No doubt much,
perhaps most, of this trend can be ascribed to the large social changes that
weakened family and community, but some of the blame can be laid at the doors
of all the well-intentioned professors who helped undermine the schools’
traditional mission of morally edifying their pupils.
Few
thinkers have written about individual autonomy with greater passion and good
sense than the nineteenth-century philosopher John Stuart Mill. Mill clearly is
talking about adults. “We are not speaking of children,” he says inOn Liberty.20 “Nobody
denies that people should be so taught and trained in youth as to know and
benefit by the ascertained results of human experience.” Mill could not foresee
the advent of thinkers like the Sizers and the values clarificationists who
glibly recommended scrapping the old morality.
Progressive
educators who follow Rousseau are at pains to preserve the child’s autonomy.
They frown on old-fashioned moralizing, preaching, and threats of punishment,
regard such methods as coercive, and believe instead that children should
discover for themselves, by their own rational faculties, which actions are
moral. This laissez-aller policy abandons children to their fate. The purpose
of moral education is not to preserve our children’s autonomy, but to develop
the character they will rely on as adults. As Aristotle persuasively argues,
children who have been helped to develop good moral habits will find it easier
to become autonomous adults. Conversely, children who have been left to their
own devices will founder.
Those who
oppose directive moral education often call it a form of brainwashing or
indoctrination. That is sheer confusion. When you brainwash people, you
undermine their autonomy, their rational selfmastery. You diminish their
freedom. But when you educate children to be competent, self-controlled and
morally responsible, you increase their freedom and enlarge their humanity. The
Greeks and Romans understood this very well. So did the great scholastic and
enlightenment thinkers. Indeed, a first principle of every great religion and
high civilization is to know what is right and act on it. This is the highest expression
of freedom and personal autonomy. To suggest that we place more emphasis on
instilling a sense of responsibility and civility than on alerting children to
their civil and personal rights under law may sound quaint, quixotic, or even
reactionary but is practical and achievable. Despite appearances to the
contrary, most children respect civility and good manners. If their own manners
are wanting, it is because so little is expected of them.
Common
sense, convention, tradition, and even modern social science21 research
all converge in support of the Aristotelian tradition 21. See, for example,
Laurence Steinberg in Beyond the Classroom: Why
School of directive character education. Children need standards, they need clear
guidelines, they need adults in their lives who are understanding but firmly
insistent on responsible behavior, but a resolute adherence to standards has
been out of fashion in education circles for more than thirty years. An
Aristotelian education is still the child’s best bet. Unfortunately, our era
has been characterized by the ascendancy of Rousseau and a decided antipathy
toward the directive inculcation of the virtues.
In April
1999, the massacre at Columbine High School shocked an uncomprehending nation
by its cold brutality. It was the seventh school shooting in less than two
years. This time, more than ever, the public’s need to make sense of such
tragedies was palpable. How could it happen? The usual explanations made little
sense. Poverty? Eric Harris and Dylan Klebold were not poor. Easy access to
weapons? True, but young men, especially in the West, have always had access to
guns. Divorce? Both boys’ families were intact. A nation of emotionally
repressed boys? Boys were much the same back in the fifties and sixties when
nobody shot up schoolmates. And why American boys?
Asking,
Why now? and, Why here? puts us on the track of what is missing in the American
way of socializing children that was present in the recent past. To find
answers, we need to attend to the views of the progressive-education theorists
who advocated abandoning the traditional mission of indoctrinating children in
the “old morality” and persuaded the American educational establishment to
adopt instead the romantic moral pedagogy of Rousseau. Teachers and parents who
embraced this view badly underestimated the potential barbarism of children who
are not given a directive moral education. It is not likely that a single
ethics course would have been enough to stop boys like Harris and Klebold from
murdering classmates. On the other hand, a K-12 curriculum infused with moral
content might have created a climate that would make a massacre unthinkable.
For such a depraved and immoral act was indeed unthinkable in the simpleminded
days before the schools cast aside their mission of moral edification. An
insistence on character education might have diminished the derisive
mistreatment at the hands of more popular students suffered by the
perpetrators, which apparently was one incitement for their gruesome actions.
Teachers,
too, would have acted differently. Had K-12 teachers in the Littleton schools seen
it as their routine duty to civilize the students in their care, they would
never have overlooked the bizarre, antisocial behavior of Klebold and Harris.
When the boys appeared in school with T-shirts with the words “Serial Killer”
emblazoned on them, their teachers would have sent them home, nor would the
boys have been allowed to wear swastikas or to produce grotesquely violent
videos. By tolerating these modes of self-expression, the adults at Columbine
High School implicitly sent the message to the students that there’s not much
wrong with the serial or mass murder of innocent people.
One
English teacher at Columbine told Education Week that both
boys had written short stories about death and killing “that were horribly, graphically,
violent” and that she had notified school officials. According to the teacher,
they took no action because nothing the boys wrote violated school policy.
Speaking with painful irony, the frustrated teacher explained, “In a free
society, you can’t take action until they’ve committed some horrific crime
because they are guaranteed freedom of speech.”22 In many
high schools, students are confident that their right to free expression will
be protected. Counselors and administrators, fearful of challenges by litigious
parents who would be backed by the ACLU and other zealous guardians of
students’ rights, rarely take action. The love affair with Rousseau’s romantic
idealization of the child of American education has made it inevitable that our
public schools fail to do their part in civilizing young “barbarians.” Many
schools no longer see themselves having a primary role in moral edification.
The style is not to interfere with the child’s self-expression and autonomy. Leaving
children to discover their own values is a little like putting them in a
chemistry lab full of volatile substances and saying, “Discover your own
compounds, kids.” We should not be surprised when some blow themselves up and
destroy those around them.
Even
before the spate of school shootings raised public concern about the moral
climate in the nation’s schools, voices called for reform. In the early
nineties, a hitherto silent majority of parents, teachers, and community
leaders began to agitate in favor of old-fashioned moral education. In July
1992, one group called the Character Counts Coalition (organized by the
Josephson Institute of Ethics and made up of teachers, youth leaders,
politicians, and ethicists) gathered in Aspen, Colorado, for a
three-and-a-half-day conference on character education. At the end of the
conference, the group put forward the Aspen Declaration on Character Education.23 Among its
principles:
• The
present and future well-being of our society requires an involved, caring
citizenry with good moral character.
• Effective
character education is based on core ethical values which form the foundation
of democratic society—in particular, respect, responsibility, trustworthiness,
caring, justice, fairness, civic virtue, and citizenship.
•
Character education is, first and foremost, an obligation of families. It is
also an important obligation of faith communities, schools, youth and other
human service organizations.
The
Character Counts Coalition has attracted a wide and politically diverse
following. Its board of advisers includes liberals such as Marian Wright
Edelman and conservatives such as William Bennett. Ten United States senators
from both political parties have joined, along with a number of governors,
mayors, and state representatives. The new character education movement is
gaining impetus.
Today,
schools throughout the country are finding their way back to contemporary
versions of directive moral education. Teachers, administrators, and parents
are again getting into the business of making it clear to students that they
must behave honorably, courteously, and kindly, that they must work hard and
strive for excellence. Several state departments of education and numerous
large-city boards of education, including those of St. Louis, Chicago,
Hartford, and San Antonio, have mandated an ethics curriculum. In some schools
the whole curriculum is shaped by these imperatives.
Fallon
Park Elementary School in Roanoke, Virginia, for example, has seen a dramatic
change in its students since the principal adopted the Character Counts program
in 1998.24 Every morning the students recite the Pledge of Allegiance. This is
followed by a pledge written by the students and teachers: “Each day in our
words and actions we will persevere to exhibit respect, caring, fairness, trustworthiness,
responsibility and citizenship. These qualities will help us to be successful students
who work and play well together.” According to the principal, suspensions have
declined sixty percent, attendance and grades have improved, and—mirabile
dictu—misbehavior on the bus has all but disappeared. The school’s gym
instructor, who has been there for twenty-nine years, has noticed a change. The
kids are practicing good sportsmanship, and even school troublemakers seem to
be changing for the better. She recently noticed one such boy encouraging a shy
girl to join a game. “It almost brought tears to my eyes . . . this is the best
year ever in this school.”
Vera
White, principal of Jefferson Junior High in Washington, D.C., was stunned some
years ago to realize that children from her school had been part of an angry
mob that attacked police and firefighters with rocks and bottles. “Those are my
children. If they didn’t care enough to respect the mayor and the fire marshal
and everyone else, what good does an education do?” She decided to make
character education central to the mission of her school. Students now attend assemblies
that focus on positive traits such as respect and responsibility. Ms. White
initiated the program in 1992; since then theft and fighting have been rare.
Unlike other schools in the area, Jefferson has no bars on the windows and no
metal detectors.25
William
F. Washington Jarvis, headmaster at the Roxbury Latin School in Boston and an
Episcopal priest, has always emphasized character and discipline, but others
are now joining him. Jarvis holds a harsh, non-Rousseauian view of human
nature: left untrained, we are “brutish, selfish, and capable of great cruelty.
We must do our utmost to be decent and responsible, and we must demand this of
our children and our students.” Whenever they behave badly, says the
headmaster, “We have to hold up a mirror to the students and say, ‘This is who
you are. Stop it.’”26
Contrast
these schools with a school like Columbine High. We know that the Littleton
killers had attended anger-management seminars, met weekly with a “diversion”
officer, attended a Mothers Against Drunk Driving panel, and did compulsory
community service. But it seems they never encountered a Reverend Jarvis or a
Principal White. After Littleton, many a barn door is being shut and padlocked,
but a spokesperson for the Littleton school district had it right when she
asked, “Do you make a high school into an armed prison camp where there are
metal detectors that make kids feel imprisoned, or do you count on people’s
basic goodness and put good rules in place?”27
One very
promising program for putting good rules in place is the Youth Charter,
developed by William Damon, a professor of education at Stanford University and
a leading authority on moral education.28 Damon’s
program calls for communities to work out a code of conduct for children. Youth
Charter helps parents and schools set rules and standards that make clear to
children what is expected of them.
Although
the movement to reinstate directive moral education is gathering momentum, it
is being fiercely resisted in some quarters by those who find it educationally
retrograde. Amherst professor Benjamin DeMott wrote a scathing piece for Harper’s magazine
a few years ago jeering at the reviving character education movement. He asked
how we can hope to teach ethics in a society where CEOs award themselves large
salaries in the midst of downsizing. Thomas Lasley, Dean of the University of
Dayton School of Education, denounces what he calls the values juggernaut.
Alfie Kohn, a noted education speaker and writer, accuses schools that are
active in character education of indoctrinating children and blighting them
politically. “Children in American schools are even expected to begin each day
by reciting a loyalty oath to the Fatherland, although we call it by a
different name.”29 Kohn’s comparison—likening
the Pledge of Allegiance to a loyalty oath in Hitler’s Reich—is a fair example
of the mindset one still finds among some progressives.
Will the
educational philosophy of the Kohns, Lasleys, De Motts, and Sizers prevail? The
answer is “no, not any longer.” It appears that parents, teachers, school
administrators, and community leaders have finally been alerted and alarmed,
and are beginning to assert their wills. Programs like Character Counts and the
Youth Charter are flourishing and new programs are starting up all the time.
Nan Dearen, executive director of Kids with Character in Dallas, has
characterized this momentum: “They say character education is a grassroots
movement, but it just spreads like wildfire.”30 Kevin
Ryan, director of the Center for the Advancement of Ethics and Character at
Boston University, expresses the movement’s confidence and resolve: “Society
will not put up with value-neutral education.”31
* * *
Social
critics often refer to the Law of Unintended Consequences. According to this
law, seemingly benign social or political changes often have unfortunate, even
disastrous, side effects. Few romantic idealists of the 1920s and 1930s, for
example, had any idea that applying utopian principles to real societies might
cause their total degradation. Nor did anyone in the 1970s expect that applying
Rousseau’s perspective to moral education would set children adrift, denying to
them the essential guidance they need in life. Fortunately, a Law of Fortuitous
Reversals also operates in social life. According to this second law, when bad,
unintended consequences seem irreparable, the situation suddenly improves dramatically.
One fortuitous reversal was the rapid, unforeseen disintegration of the Soviet
system a decade ago. Another, just under way, is the unexpected return of
Aristoteliancommon sense in the moral education of American children.
1. R. S.
Peters, “Concrete Principles and Rational Passions.” In Moral
Education: Five Lectures, Nancy F. and Theodore R.
Sizer, eds. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970): 29.
2.
“Ethical Choices: Individual Voices” (New York: Thirteen/WNET, 1997).
3.
Aristotle, Ethics, trans. J.A.K. Thomson (London: Penguin,
1976): 109.
4. ———. Ethics: 92.
5. From
Steven Cahn, ed. “Emile.” In The Philosophical
Foundations of Education (New York: Harper &
Row, 1970): 163. Selection from The ‘Emile’ of Jean-Jacques
Rousseau: Selections, William Boyd, ed. (New
York: Teachers College, Columbia University, 1962): 11–128.
6.
William Boyd, ed. The ‘Emile’ of Jean-Jacques Rousseau. (New
York: Teachers College Press, 1970): 41.
7. Steven
Cahn, The Philosophical Foundations of Education: 158.
8. Ibid.,
162.
9. Ibid.,
174.
10. He is
said to have fathered five illegitimate children by an uneducated servant girl, Te´rese Le Vasseur. All the children were sent
to foundling homes, which was the equivalent of a death sentence. See Ronald
Grimsley, “Jean-Jacques Rousseau,” in Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 7
(New York: Macmillan, 1967): 218.
11. Cahn,
The Philosophical Foundations of Education: 160.
12.
Ibid., 163.
13. Nancy
F. and Theodore R. Sizer, eds. Moral Education: Five
Lectures.
14.
Ibid., 3–5.
15.
Ibid., 4.
16.
Sidney Simon and Howard Kirschenbaum, Readings in Values
Clarification (Minneapolis, Minn.: Winston Press, 1973):
18.
17. See,
for example, Lawrence Kohlberg, “The Cognitive-Developmental Approach,” Phi Delta
Kappan (June 1975): 670–75.
18. See
Lawrence Kohlberg, “Moral Education Reappraised,” The Humanist (November/
December 1978): 14–15. Kohlberg, renouncing his earlier position, said: Some
years of active involvement with the practice of moral education . . . has led
me to realize that my notion . . . was mistaken . . . The educator must be a
socializer, teaching value content and behavior and not [merely] . . . a
process-facilitator of development . . . Ino longer hold these negative views
of indoctrinative moral education and I [now] believe that the concepts guiding
moral education must be partly ‘indoctrinative.’ This is true, by necessity, in
a world in which children engage in stealing, cheating and aggression.”
19. Write
Source 2000 Sourcebook (Wilmington, Mass.: Houghton
Mifflin, 1995): 217.
20. John
Stuart Mill, On Liberty (Chicago: Regnery Press,
1955): 14.
21. Reform
Has Failed and What Parents Need to Do (New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1996).
22. Education
Week (April 28, 1999): 16; see also Education Week (May 26,
1999): 14.
23.
“Aspen Declaration on Character Education,” available through the Josephson
Institute, Marina Del Ray, California; or Kevin Ryan, Director, Boston
University Center for the Advancement of Ethics and Character.
24. See Washington
Post (February 4, 1999): metro, 1.
25. Dallas
Morning News (March 10, 1995): 1C.
26. Wray
Herbert and Missy Daniel, “The Moral Child,” U.S. News&World Report (June 3,
1996): 52.
27. Education
Week (April 28, 1999): 17.
28.
William Damon, The Youth Charter: How Communities Can Work
Together to Raise Standards for All Our Children (New York: Free Press,
1997).
29. Alfie
Kohn, “How Not to Teach Values: A Critical Look at Character Education,” Phi Delta
Kappan (February 1997): 433.
30.
Colleen O’Connor, “The We Decade: Rebirth of Community,” The
Dallas Morning News (March 10, 1995): 1.
31. Scott
Baldauf, “Reading, Writing, and Right and Wrong,” The Christian Science Monitor
(August 27, 1996): 1.
==============================
Marvin W.
Berkowitz
The
field of character education is rife with controversy as debates question whether
the focus should be on virtues, values, behaviors, or reasoning capacities.
Controversy swirls around the varied approaches to implementing character
education: experiential learning, peer debate, indoctrinative teaching,
community service, participatory governance, reading about character, and so
on. Many of these debates have strong roots in theoretical and philosophical
differences. However, when and if the dust settles, it should be clear that the
bottom line of character education is not philosophical distinctions, pedagogical
ideologies, politics, or other conceptual disagreements. Rather, it is the
development of children. In this chapter, I will attempt to take a very focused
and practical approach to character education, to take a stab at beginning what
can become a science of character education. I will examine what we mean by
character, how it develops, and what can be done to foster its optimal
development.
This work
was supported by a grant from the John Templeton Foundation.
Before we
can explore what we know (and don’t know) about character development and
character education, we need to discuss terminology. The labels for this field
vary by history, geography, and ideology. Currently in the United States, the
term du jour is character education.
That is
the term I have chosen to use in this chapter. However, only a decade or two
ago, the more popular term was moral education. The term moral still tends to
be preferred in many other countries, especially in Asia, although one group in
Japan has wedded the term to psychology and produced a new term, “moralogy.”
Preceding that, values education was in vogue in the United States. Values
education is, in fact, the currently preferred term in Great Britain (although
the Scottish Consultative Council on the Curriculum prefers the term values in
education whereas others in Great Britain prefer values education).
Furthermore, different theoretical perspectives are aligned more with one or
another of these various terms. In the United States, character education has
been aligned most closely with more conservative, traditional, and behavioral
approaches. Moral education has been aligned with more liberal, constructivist,
and cognitive approaches. Values education has been aligned with more
atheoretical, attitudinal, empirical approaches. At this point in the
discussion, I expect you to be quite confused and even annoyed at this degree
of terminological disagreement. I know I am. Do not panic, however, because I
will, from here on use the terms character development and character education
to represent all these disparate points of view, and you can now proceed to
forget the confusion that I have just outlined for you.
There has
been too muchof the “my theory can beat up your theory” mentality in the field.
I prefer a more dialectical approach, whereby the intersections and conflicts
between different approaches can be used to generate agreements, compromises,
and best solutions. It is time to use science to help kids become good people
rather than lay out landmines of theory disagreements.
This
diversity and disagreement have led to a rather fractionated perspective on
what I refer to as character development. In this chapter, I choose to use the
term character (only in part because I hold the title of Sanford N. McDonnell
Professor of Character Education); however, I use it as an integrative,
bridging term. One goal of this chapter is to build bridges across the
theoretical chasms that have been dug by contentious warring factions in this
field. Actually, I am rather uninterested in terminology. I would be just as
happy to call the field moral education, which I did for over two decades, or
to create a new allencompassing rubric such as developmental education. In
fact, I wouldn’t mind calling it Henrietta or Blog or 2C3a#*11.a as long as it is
defined clearly and as long as it optimally serves the development of socio-moral
competency in children. As I said before, this is all about kids, not esoteric
distinctions, labels, or factions. Those rarely serve kids’ best interests.
Just as
it is difficult to define character and find consensual labels for character
education, it is difficult to summarize what contemporary character education
entails. The term character education has come to encompass what used to be
rather different fields. I will therefore try to provide a quick and dirty
bird’s-eye view of character education. Ideally, as we shall see later in this
chapter, quality character education should be intentional and
comprehensive—sometimes it is intentional; rarely is it comprehensive. The
Character Education Partnership articulates standards for quality character
education in their “Eleven Principles of Effective Character Education” and the
corresponding “Character Education Quality Standards” (both of which can be
accessed through their website: www.character.org). These standards include an
explicit values agenda, schoolwide implementation, promoting positive
relationships and intrinsic motivation, defining character comprehensively, partnering
with parents and community, and being data-driven. It is rare to find schools
or districts that fulfill all of these standards.
Most
character education initiatives center around a set of words or concepts that
represent the ethical agenda of the school; i.e., “words of the month” (or
week, or even day) that identify the character outcomes identified as central
to the school’s mission by the school, community, or both. Those words
sometimes are chosen by the school staff, sometimes by district staff or a
community panel, and sometimes adopted from another source (such as the
Character Counts’s “six pillars of character”). What schools do with these
words is quite variable. Although sometimes they simply pay lip-service to
them, usually they display them prominently (on calendars, stationery, walls,
and so on). They may use them as the foci for curriculum or extracurricular
programming. Often character education stands alone. Frequently middle schools and
high schools put character education into homeroom or advisory class meetings
or make it an elective or required class. Character education is typically part
of the curriculum in literature and social studies classes, but it actually can
appear in almost any part of the curriculum, including math and physical
education. Many schools connect their character agenda with their service
opportunities. Although service learning is a common vehicle for character
education, any form of service may support character education.
Character
education can focus on specific issues such as sex education, health education,
environmental studies, multicultural education, peer conflict resolution, risk
prevention, and religious studies. It may focus on fostering specific character
outcomes such as moral reasoning (typically through ethical dilemma discussion)
or altruism (through service).
Character
education is less frequently manifested as comprehensive school reform. Models
such as the Just Community School, Child Development Project, Responsive
Classroom, and Resolving Conflict Creatively Program are all approaches that
stress pervasive schoolwide culture transformation. Whereas all of these and
other approaches are observed in schools, the justification for selecting one
approach over another is often less than scientific. Typically it is based on
convenience, external advocacy, limited knowledge, intuition, and so on. The
bottom line is that what stands as character education is highly variable and infrequently
meets the standards for quality. To create a true science of character
education, we need to back up and explore what we mean by character, how it
develops, and what we know about how schools can effectively foster its
development.
It is
impossible to foster optimum character development without first understanding
what comprises character. That would be tantamount to trying to build a better
mousetrap without knowing what a mouse is. It would be nice if there were
consensus on what is meant by the term character, but unfortunately, that is
not the case. In common language, we use the term to mean either some measure
of a person’s goodness (“that really shows a lack of character on his part”) or
a person’s eccentricity (“she is such a character!”). In both cases, the
implication is that we are referring to some enduring characteristic of the
person, although that is not always the case (his lack of character may be out
of character for him).
The
picture is even muddier when we examine how the term character is used
technically. Some do not systematically distinguish between moral and nonmoral
character, whereas others either restrict their definitions to the moral domain1 or
systematically separate moral from nonmoral aspects of character.2 Even when
these distinctions are made, the criteria often differ; e.g., Nucci considers
the moral domain to comprise universals,3 whereas
Lickona differentiates between universal and nonuniversal morality.4 For some,
character is pure personality, whereas for others it is mainly behavioral. Many
omit cognitive functioning from their definitions of character. Some are
comprehensive in their definitions, others not; some specific, others fairly
global. I will not spend time here listing the differing definitions of
character. I think you get the idea. Instead, I offer my own definition.
I define
character as an individual’s set of psychological
characteristics that affect that person’s ability and inclination to function
morally. Simply put, character is comprised of those characteristics that lead
a person to do the right thing or not to do the right thing. This serves as a
global definition of character. Obviously, however, I still need to define what
psychological characteristics affect moral functioning. Elsewhere, I offer what
I call the Moral Anatomy.5 By this,
I mean the psychological components that make up the complete moral person.
There are
seven parts to the moral anatomy: moral behavior, moral values, moral
personality, moral emotion, moral reasoning, moral identity, and foundational
characteristics. Whether one adopts this particular model of character or
another (such as the tripartite model of cognition, affect, and behavior—head,
heart, and hand—espoused by the Character Education Partnership and Lickona),
the point to understand here is that character is a complex psychological
concept.6 It entails the capacity to think about right and wrong, experience moral
emotions (guilt, empathy, compassion), engage in moral behaviors (sharing,
donating to charity, telling the truth), believe in moral goods, demonstrate an
enduring tendency to act with honesty, altruism, responsibility, and other
characteristics that support moral functioning.
Just as
Howard Gardner has redefined intelligence as a complex of psychological
characteristics in his theory of multiple intelligences, I attempt to redefine
character as a complex constellation of psychological dimensions of a person.
This
perspective on character provides us with a road map through the following
sections of this chapter. I amnot wedded to this particular definition, but
rather to defining character in a psychological, differentiated, and comprehensive
manner. With this or another comprehensive, differentiated definition of
character in hand, we can directly address how character develops and what can
be done to foster or nurture its development.
The
recent epidemic of heinous acts of violence by children against children, such
as the shooting of a young girl by a six-year-old boy in Flint, Michigan, has
prompted many to raise the question of when character develops. This is a
rather tricky question that I believe is fundamentally unanswerable. First, we
have just established that character is a multifaceted phenomenon. Second, the
components of character each have their own developmental trajectories. Third,
each person develops at a different rate. Fourth, the developmental sequence and
profile of the components of character differ in different individuals.
Finally,
the components of character tend to develop gradually, or in stages over a long
period of time. Hence, we cannot state that the six-year-old boy in Flint did or
did not have character. We cannot state either that six-year-olds in general do
or do not have character. Rather, we can describe what aspects of character are
typically developed (and to what degree) around six years of age. Then we can
compare that child with what is typical, being careful to remember that
children develop at different rates. For instance, if a six-year-old child
showed no remorse over hurting another, did not realize that others may have perspectives
different from his, or seemed not to care what others thought of him, we could
then say that he seemed not to be developing some aspects of character that
should be present at around his age.
Given
this perspective, it is fair to claim that character begins developing at birth
or even earlier. Because there is evidence of genetic influences on character,
we can reasonably argue for prenatal character development. There is also
evidence that parents begin to bond emotionally to a child even before birth,
and we know that the bond between parent and infant is a critical factor in
character development. It is well beyond the scope of this chapter to chronicle
developments of all of the components of character development. Instead, I will
illustrate its course by presenting developments of selected components in
infancy, childhood, and adolescence (for a more detailed presentation, see Damon7).
Some of
the earliest, most significant hallmarks of the development of character are
(1) the beginning of empathy, (2) the development of a concept of persons, and
(3) the formation of the attachment bond. All of these begin during the first
year of life.
Mature
empathy entails self-awareness, self-other differentiation, perspective-taking,
and the ability to draw inferences about the causes of another’s distress.
Martin Hoffman describes four stages of empathic development, the first of
which covers most of the first year of life and the second of which begins at
about nine or ten months of age. In the first stage the infant cries in
response to another’s crying, at first only very reflexively. (It is also
around six months when the child develops a first sense of the other as
separate from itself.) In the second stage, infants spend more time observing
the other in distress and actively attempt to reduce their own resulting
empathic distress (e.g., by thumbsucking). This self-consoling behavior reveals
the immaturity of empathy at this point; it is still focused on the self.
Nevertheless, this is the foundation of mature empathy, which is central to
mature moral functioning or character.
The
person concept refers to differentiation of self from other; that is, a
recognition that you and I are separate entities with separate agency (independent
capacities for causality) and separate existences. This begins to develop
during the first two years of life. All character components (e.g.,
perspective-taking, moral reasoning, shame, cooperation) depend upon the
development of self-other differentiation. It is impossible to be a moral agent
without first recognizing that there are other human beings in the world.
The
development of an attachment bond, the powerful emotional relationship that
develops between an infant and his or her primary caretaker (typically mother),
may be the single most important step in the development of character. The
development begins roughly in the middle of the first year of life and evolves
over the course of the life span. More important, however, it serves as a major
influence on the nature of all future relationships. It has been linked to many
other aspects of character such as peer cooperation, compliance with adults, and
altruism. In fact, the absence of the motivation to have positive relationships
with others (e.g., detachment, disinterest in social relationships) is a
symptom of psychopathology, according to the American Psychiatric Association.
The failure to form a secure attachment bond early in life may be the most
significant cause of childhood antisocial behavior.
These
diverse aspects of character (and others not described here) in the first two
years of life are the foundation for later mature character and represent the
first stages of character formation.
So much
of character develops during childhood that it is difficult to select a few
examples for this discussion. Nevertheless, I will examine three: self-control,
guilt, and perspective-taking.
Whereas
self-control begins, in a sense, with the compliance of the toddler, the full
capacity to regulate one’s own impulses internally makes the greatest headway
during the preschool years, especially between the ages of five and seven.
Consequently, children are better able to delay gratification, control their
impulses and aggressive urges, and direct their behavior. Roy Baumeister argues
that self-control is a master virtue upon which other virtues depend.
Given the
current interest in problems caused by children who seem not to have developed
a conscience, the development of guilt feelings is of critical importance in
understanding character development. Guilt is typically described as a
self-critical emotional response to one’s own transgressions. Thomas Lickona
differentiates between constructive guilt (self-criticism leading to motivation
for improvement) and destructive guilt (lowered self-esteem and
self-denigration). For the development of character, we are clearly interested
in the former. Grazyna Kochanska and her colleagues have found guilt feelings
to increase significantly from two to three or four years after first emerging
at about eighteen to twenty-four months.
Perspective-taking
develops throughout the preschool and elementary school years, and its
development continues throughout adolescence. There is some evidence that
children as young as twenty-four to thirty months of age can do some
rudimentary perspective-taking; however, the major advances in the capacity to
understand others’ points of view occur between three or four years and twelve
years of age. Because moral functioning depends upon the ability to balance
different people’s interests, perspective-taking development is a critical
foundational component of character. Clearly, key components of character
become fully operative during the childhood years, making childhood a significant
point for the transition to being a mature social and moral agent.
Most
character development in adolescence is a continuation of what has already
begun in infancy or childhood. I will examine the continued development of
moral reasoning and the formation of a moral identity as two examples of
adolescent character development.
Moral
reasoning is the growth of the cognitive capacity to reason about matters of
right and wrong, allowing for increasingly effective and mature moral
decision-making and moral judgment. Moral reasoning is understood to develop in
stages throughout the life span, beginning as young as three or four years of
age. However, it is only at about eleven or twelve, as the child enters
adolescence, that moral reasoning becomes predominantly prosocial, although the
beginnings of such considerations are evident in the elementary school years.
As children move through adolescence, their criteria for judging right and
wrong shift from mostly self-oriented concerns with concrete consequences to themselves,
to more socially oriented concerns with the impact of their behaviors on
others, their relationships with others, and the social organizations of which
they are members. The ability to figure out what is right and what is wrong is
crucial as all people confront novel or ambiguous moral problems and true
dilemmas. Furthermore, moral reasoning is related to a variety of moral and
immoral behaviors such as altruism, cheating, delinquency, and risky behaviors
(such as unsafe sexual practices and drug use).
Identity
is the individual’s self-constructed sense of self. Recent interest has turned
to the concept of moral identity, the centrality of being good to one’s
self-concept, because of its appearance in studies of living and hypothetical
moral exemplars. Adolescence is a critical time for the formation of a sense of
self, an identity. Therefore, it is likely that the formation of a sense of
oneself as a moral agent develops at the same time.
If
science can reveal what character is and how it develops, what can it tell us
about how adults and society can actively promote the development of character
in children? After all, it is up to adults and society to ensure that children
have the opportunity to develop into competent moral adults, both for the sake
of children and for the benefit of society. Family (especially parents) is
typically considered the predominant influence on a child’s character
formation. Additionally, school, peers, community (including the media),
religion, and biology are contributors. It is clear that how parents raise a
child is the predominant influence on the child’s character formation. Some of
the operative variables are parental affection, consistency of parenting,
response to children’s cues and signals, modeling, expression of values,
respect for the child, and open discussion with the child. All aspects of
children’s character are impacted by these and other child-rearing factors.
School
has an influence later than parenting because (1) parents are much more
emotionally salient in the first years of life, and (2) many children do not
experience full or even part-time schooling until they are three, four or five
years of age, when, as we have just seen, many aspects of character are already
developing. Schools can influence a child’s self-concept (including
self-esteem), social skills (especially peer social skills), values, moral
reasoning maturity, prosocial inclinations and behavior, knowledge about morality,
values, and so on.
The
influence of peers begins in the preschool years, especially for children who
attend preschools, but this influence clearly increases throughout childhood
and peaks in adolescence. Peers have a strong effect on self-concept, social
skills (e.g., conflict resolution, making and maintaining friendships), moral
reasoning development, involvement in risky behaviors, and so on.
Community
influences center around mass media exposure, neighborhood characteristics, and
cultural values. Media clearly affect prejudice (racism, sexism, ageism),
aggression, and sense of security. Religion has been related to lower risk
behavior and greater mental health. The evidence about biology is much more
controversial. Some argue for a strong genetic influence on aspects of
character (altruism, risktaking) and others suggest a much lesser role for
genetics. Other biological factors have also been implicated, but only in
extreme cases, such as in utero exposure to teratogens (such as opiates,
alcohol) and serious disease factors.
Developmental
psychology has much more to tell us about the effects of parenting on
children’s character development than other influences, including schooling.
For that reason, John Grych and I examined the research literature for
information about how parenting influences character development in children.
What we discovered is that (1) much relevant research already exists, (2) a
common core of parenting variables that promote character development can be
identified from an empirical base, and (3) those parenting variables can also
be applied to teacher behavior and character education.
We
identified eight character variables extensively studied by developmental psychologists:
social orientation (attachment), self-control, compliance, self-esteem,
empathy, conscience, moral reasoning, and altruism. You will recognize some of
these from the discussion above. We looked at what research has uncovered about
the effect of parental behavior on the development of those eight character
outcomes. We were able to identify five parenting behaviors that were
significantly related to at least two of the eight character outcomes. Responsivity/
nurturance was related to six of the eight outcomes (all
but empathy and self-control). Parents who were responsive to children’s
signals and needs and had a warm, loving relationship with their children
produced children of strong, multifaceted character. Families who used an open,
democratic style of family discussion, decision-making, and problemsolving produced
children who exhibited five characteristics (all but empathy, self-control, and
social orientation). Parents who used induction
(praising or disciplining with explanations that include a focus on the
consequences of the child’s behavior for other’s feelings) produced children
with relatively more mature empathy, conscience, altruism and moral reasoning.
Parents who set high expectations (demandingness) that
were attainable and supported, had children who were high in self-control,
altruism, and self-esteem. Parents who modeled selfcontrol
and altruism had children high in self-control and altruism. Additional
research will likely expand the list.
We can
clearly mine the rich empirical literature in developmental psychology to
better understand character development and what influences it. We know much
about how parenting affects character and can easily apply this knowledge to
schools, especially to teacher behavior.
Few
approaches to character education have been extensively researched. One of
those, values clarification, has largely disappeared from the scene, in part
due to generally ineffective scientific evidence. Extensive research on
classroom dilemma discussion has demonstrated that it effectively promotes the
development of moral reasoning capacities in students, and much is known about
how it works. A detailed study of the Just Community Schools approach has
demonstrated its effectiveness in promoting moral reasoning and stimulating the
development of positive school culture and prosocial norms. The I-can-problem-solve
approach to preventing impulsive and inhibited behaviors has been demonstrated
repeatedly to be an effective means of reducing such behaviors in young school
children.
The most
extensive body of scientifically sound research about a comprehensive character
education approach concerns the Child Development Project (a program of the
Development Studies Center in Oakland, Calif., www.devstu.org). This elementary
school reform program has been shown to promote prosocial behavior, reduce
risky behaviors, stimulate academic motivation, create a positive school
community, result in higher grades, and foster democratic values.
Furthermore,
it has identified the development of a caring school community as the critical
mediating factor in the effectiveness of character education.
Numerous
other character education initiatives and programs report single studies of
effectiveness, but are not often reviewed and published. The best examples are
the Responsive Classroom, Second Step, Positive Action, and the Resolving
Conflict Creatively Program. Solomon, Watson, and Battistich have compiled an
extensive review of specific research studies about such programs and specific
practices in implementing character education.8 They
conclude that four practices have strong empirical support for promoting
character development: promoting student autonomy and influence; student
participation, discussion, and collaboration; social skills training; and
helping and social service behavior. An additional important mediating variable
is moral atmosphere. The Child Development Project uses the term caring
community and applies it both to the classroom and the entire school. The
degree to which children perceive their schools as caring communities is
directly related to the effectiveness of those schools in promoting student
character development. Just Community Schools defines the variable somewhat
differently, but reports that promotion of the development of moral atmosphere
in the school is directly linked to the development of moral reasoning in
students, and this finding has been internationally replicated. One solution to
the lack of an empirical foundation on which to build a science of character
education is to mine other fields for scientific evidence relevant to character
education.
A fertile
area to explore for relevant scientific research is risk-prevention. Alan
Leschner, director of the National Institute on Drug Abuse, recently argued
that prevention is generic and entails identifying those factors that protect
against the risk factors that promote undesirable and dangerous behaviors.
Other leaders in the field frequently echo this sentiment. Drug-use prevention
researchers increasingly recognize that character-based interventions can
effectively prevent substance use and abuse, just as character educators
discover that their initiatives are preventive. Likewise, two of the most
effective violenceprevention curricula, Second Step and Resolving Conflict
Creatively, have been identified by the Character Education Partnership as
character education initiatives. At the same time, the most effective character
education program, the Child Development Project, is identified by the Department
of Education as a model violence-prevention program and by the Center for
Substance Abuse Prevention as a model prevention program. Others argue for the
application of character education as a form of sex education. Furthermore,
reviews of such tangentially related fields reveal striking parallels in what
works.
Although
much more research needs to be done to better understand what does and does not
work, there is enough information available to reach some conclusions. The
following represent seven rules of thumb for effective character education
based on the research literature to date. First, it is clear that the primary
influence on a child’s character development is how
people treat the child. When schools focus on exhortations
(PA announcements, posters, lecturers at special assemblies) or didactics
(curriculum) as they are typically disposed to do, they miss the boat. To do
effective character education, either in the home or the school, one has to
focus on how people (especially those most significant to the child, but not
only them) treat the child. What is the child’s experience in spending a day in
school? Is that child treated benevolently and with respect, or bullied or
ignored? Does the child perceive school and classroom as nurturant, supportive
places or as psychologically or physically toxic? Relationships are crucial to
character development, so character education must focus on the quality of relationships
in the school. This includes adult-to-child and child-to-child relationships.
We can readily extrapolate from the parenting literature to adult and student
relationships. Those relationships need to be benevolent (nurturant,
supportive), authentic (honest, open), respectful (inclusive, valuing the
student’s voice), and consistent (predictable, stable). Most of the recent
spate of school murders have implicated experiences of peer bullying as part of
the cause of those horrors. Quality character education promotes prosocial
relationships and caring school and classroom communities.
Second,
we know that children learn, and their development is influenced by, what they
observe, so the second principal factor in effective quality character
education is how significant others treat other people in
the child’s presence, as Theodore and Nancy
Sizer note in the title of their recent book The
Students Are Watching. Parents are well aware
that their children monitor and retain much of what they observe teachers and
other adults in the school doing. Teachers are likewise well aware that
students, even very young ones, report a wide variety of family behavior in the
classroom. In both cases the observed and reported behaviors are often ones the
adult models did not even realize were being registered or even observed, and
in many cases they are behaviors they would rather were not observed at all and
certainly not broadcast publicly. Students are indeed watching. What is worse
is that they are also imitating. Elementary school teachers have taught me that
if you want to know what kind of teacher you are, simply watch your students
playing school. Modeling of positive behaviors such as altruism and empathy
leads to such behavior in children. Modeling of undesirable behaviors such as
violence and deceit similarly leads to the increase in those behaviors. It is
pointless to expect children to be respectful and responsible if the adults in
their lives do not act respectfully and responsibly. Many educators argue that
they are not character educators and often that they do not want to be. If you
work with or around children, you cannot not be a
character educator. Abstaining is not an option.
Your behavior will affect children’s character development, for good or for
ill. Cleaning up our acts and walking the talk is necessary for character
education to be effective.
Third,
schools need to expect good character of all members. In
other words, character needs to be a clear priority and expectation—schools must
demand good character. The expectations should be clear, they should be high
but attainable, and there should be support structures to give students and
other school members a reasonable chance of meeting those expectations. These
expectations can come from a variety of sources, but ideally they come from the
entire school community. All stakeholder groups should at least have some
representation in the process of either generating or ratifying (if they come
from another source) those expectations.
Previously,
I stated that exhortations are not the primary means of affecting character development.
There is nonetheless a place for espousing positive
character. It serves two functions. First, it can reinforce what children learn
and develop from watching and being treated positively by others. Secondly, it
clarifies the often unclear messages of behavior. The powerful moral parenting
behavior called induction works largely because it entails explanations of
parent evaluative behavior (praising, chastising). So, as Thomas Lickona has
taught us, we need not only to practice what we preach, but we also need to
preach what we practice.
Children
also need opportunities to practice good character. They need
schools that promote student autonomy and influence. They need the opportunity
to build skills such as perspective-taking, critical thinking, and conflict
resolution, necessary for being a person of character. They also need
opportunities to do good. Schools increasingly promote service activities of a
variety of natures. Peer mediation, student selfgovernance, and charitable
activities are examples of such opportunities. To nurture the development of
moral thinking capacities, students need opportunities
to reason about, debate, and reflect on moral issues. This
includes opportunities to take others’ perspectives, especially when those
perspectives are different from one’s own. This can be done within the
curriculum, as in lessons and methods that promote student peer discussion of
moral issues embedded in social studies and literature, or case studies in
science or philosophy. It can also be done in stand-alone classes and programs
that focus on issues of character and morality. The key is to create the kind
of atmosphere in which students engage their peers to discuss such issues and
in which they feel socially safe to do so honestly and forthrightly. Educators
often need assistance in creating such an atmosphere, but that is essential for
schools to effectively promote character development in students.
Finally,
it is preferable if parents are actively and
positively involved in the school’s character education efforts. There
is decidedly less scientific evidence to support this suggestion, but
extrapolations from other areas of study clearly support the fact that parents
will always be the primary influences on children’s character development.
Character education is most effective when schools and parents work in
partnership.
Thus far
the analysis has been restricted to the typical years of elementary and
secondary schooling, roughly ages six to eighteen, the kindergarten through
high school years. Colleges and universities are also interested in
contributing to the formation of character in the future citizens of our
society. Having had the privilege of serving as the inaugural Ambassador
Holland H. Coors Professor of Character Development at the United States Air
Force Academy in 1999, I became very interested in what postsecondary education
can offer to the character development of students. Lt. Colonel (Retired)
Michael J. Fekula and I wrote an article detailing the principal components of
postsecondary character education. They are:
•
Teaching about character (morality, ethics)
•
Displaying character (both by individuals and by the institution through its
policies)
•
Demanding character
•
Practice in character (through apprenticeship, participation in school
governance, community service, and experiential learning)
•
Reflecting on character (verbally, in writing, and so on)
You will
recognizemany of these components from our prior discussion. However, what institutions
like military academies and religiously affiliated colleges and universities (I
spent twenty years teaching at Marquette University, a Jesuit institution in
Milwaukee) bring to the table (at least potentially) is consistent,
well-supported, and justified wholeinstitution commitment to character
education. That is a remarkably valuable commodity in promoting character in
schools and elsewhere.
Given the
nascent state of the new “science of character education,” many questions
remain unanswered.
• What
are the long-term effects of character education?
• Which
components of comprehensive character education models impact which components
of character?
• What
are the most critical components of effective character education?
• How
does effective character education vary from elementary to middle to high
school?
• What is
the overlap between effective character education and effective school-based
prevention and service learning?
• How can
we most effectively measure character?
• What is
the “dose response” for effective character education; that is, how much is
enough to make a difference?
• What
existing forms of education impede the fostering of character?
• Must
character education be schoolwide or can it be effectively implemented at the
classroom level?
These are
but a few important questions left for character scientists to answer. As more
research is done, many more questions will surface. But if we work to develop a
true science of character education, based on an empirical understanding of
character development and those interventions that foster character
development, then we will be wellarmed to make a significant contribution, not
only to our children, but to the world in which they and we live.
1. L. Kohlberg,
The Psychology of Moral Development, Essays on Moral Development, Vol. 2
(New York: Harper and Row, 1984).
2. M. W.
Berkowitz, “The Complete Moral Person: Anatomy and Formation” in J. M. DuBois,
ed., Moral Issues in Psychology: Personalist Contributions to Selected
Problems (Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1997): 11–42.
3. L.
Nucci, Education in the Moral Domain (New York: Praeger, 2001).
4. T.
Lickona, Educating for Character (New York: Bantam, 1991).
5. See M.
W. Berkowitz, 1997.
6. See
Lickona, 1991.
7. W.
Damon, The Moral Child (New York: Free Press,
1988).
8. D.
Solomon, M. S. Watson and V. A. Battistich, “Teaching and Schooling Effects on
Moral/Pro-Social Development” in V. Richardson, ed., Handbook
of Research on Teaching, 4th ed. (Washington,
D.C.: Association for Supervision and Curriculum Development, 2001).
==============================
Lawrence
J. Walker
The
field of moral psychology and moral education has stagnated seemingly, because of
the conceptual skew and biases of dominant models. These models provide a
threadbare conception of moral functioning and ineffectual means by which to
foster children’s moral development. I have two primary concerns. The first is
that the field has been overly focused on moral rationality because of the
influence of the formalist tradition in moral philosophy and the
cognitive-developmental tradition in moral psychology with their aversion to
personality factors, which they regard as corrupting influences on the purity
of moral reason. The second concern is that the field has been preoccupied with
the interpersonal aspects of morality that regulate our relationships with each
other while ignoring the intrapsychic aspects that pertain more to our basic
values, lifestyle, identity, and character. In this chapter I advocate a new
direction for the field, stressing the development of moral personality,
character, and virtue—a new direction that will be illustrated through the
study of moral exemplarity.
Foundational
to the present enterprise is some shared understanding of what is meant by
“morality.” Here I propose a working definition of
morality and, in doing so, make explicit my own assumptions and understandings.
I amquite aware of the recurrent controversies in moral philosophy regarding
any such definition, and do not claim to have any resolution; I only intend to
make clear my starting point. The definition is purposely broad, erring on the
side of being overly inclusive rather than narrow. In my view, morality is a
fundamental, pervasive aspect of human functioning, having both interpersonal
and intrapersonal components. More specifically, it refers to voluntary actions
that, at least potentially, have some social and interpersonal implications and
that are governed by intrapsychic cognitive and emotive mechanisms. There are a
few things to note about this tentative definition. First, morality is clearly
an interpersonal enterprise because it regulates people’s interactions and
adjudicates conflicts—it involves the impact of our behavior on others’ rights
and welfare. But morality is also an intrapersonal enterprise because it is
integral to the how-shall-we-thenlive existential question—it involves basic
values, lifestyle, and identity. These intrapsychic aspects of moral
functioning do have indirect implications for interpersonal interactions (as
the above definition claims) because our values and moral character are played
out in our relationships with others. The interpersonal aspects of moral
functioning, with their focus on interpersonal rights and welfare, have been
well represented in contemporary moral psychology and education but that has not
been the case for the intrapsychic aspects. Dominant theories in moral
psychology define the domain rather selectively and ignore issues of what has
been pejoratively labeled private morality such as the development of the self
and personal values.
The
second thing about this definition of morality is that it claims that moral
functioning is multifaceted, involving the dynamic interplay of thought,
emotion, and behavior. Moral emotions such as guilt or empathy always occur
with some accompanying cognitions, thoughts about one’s personal values or
one’s interactions with others always entail some affect, and voluntary behaviors
always have some basis in intentions that determine their moral quality. The
interactive nature of moral functioning has been destructively minimized by the
major theoretical traditions in the field, each of which has regarded different
aspects of psychological functioning as representing the core of morality—the
social-learning tradition has emphasized the acquisition of moral behaviors
through principles of learning, the identification-internalization (psychoanalytic)
tradition has emphasized the operation of moral emotions and defense mechanisms
through the dynamics of identification with parents, and the
cognitive-developmental tradition has emphasized the development of moral
judgment through individuals’ construction of meaning. This artificial trichotomy—represented
by these major competing traditions in moral psychology—obfuscates the
interdependent nature of thought, emotion, and behavior in moral functioning
and trivializes our understanding by an exclusive focus on some particular
component that has been hived off. A more comprehensive and holistic
appreciation of how these different aspects relate to each other is a pressing
goal for moral psychology.
These
competing perspectives in moral psychology have not been meaningfully
integrated and are somewhat out of balance. Taking poetic license, I contend
that contemporary moral psychology has been afflicted by rational
planexia—acondition of wandering astray, of being pulled out of proper
[planetary] alignment by the “gravity” of moral rationality. Moral psychology,
like so many other disciplines within the social sciences and beyond, has been
inordinately influenced by the legacy of the Enlightenment which, among other
things, was concerned with establishing a rational basis for moral understandings
and convictions to overcome the perils of ethical relativism. Note that this
preoccupation with the rational foundations for morality supplanted the
centuries-old ethical concern with moral virtues and character (the Aristotelian
tradition), the concern that perhaps better accords with commonsense notions of
moral life.
The
dominant philosophical perspective girdling the field has been the formalist
tradition, best exemplified by Immanuel Kant, with its assumptions emphasizing
individualism, justice, rights, and duties. Kant holds a dualistic view of
human nature—reason versus passion—with rationality forming the core of moral
functioning and personological factors (emotions, desires, personal projects,
and so on) regarded with much suspicion, as corrupting biases to overcome if
people are to attain to the standard of autonomous moral rationality.
Similarly,
the prevailing psychological framework in moral psychology has been the
structuralist cognitive-developmental tradition, exemplified by Lawrence Kohlberg,
with its assumptions emphasizing the stage-like development of moral reasoning
abilities. The structuralist tradition has not been alone in this cognitive
emphasis. Psychology, in general, has been subjected to a veritable cognitive
revolution as psychoanalytic and behavioral theories have been eclipsed by
cognitive and information-processing approaches, reflecting the liberal
optimism that arose in the period following the Second World War. Kohlberg can
be credited with overcoming much of the philosophical naı¨vete´ of early
research on morality and with establishing moral development as a legitimate
field of psychological inquiry.1 His model
has dominated moral psychology for almost three decades, and perhaps rightly
so, for his conceptual, empirical, and applied contributions have been
monumental.
Few would
quibble with that claim, and even people who disagree with Kohlberg frequently
rely on his theory as a foil. Their responses are often framed by the
fundamental assumptions undergirding his model, illustrating its profound
influence. Kohlberg’s formalist and structuralist heritage led him to focus on
moral reasoning development, assessed through individuals’ cerebrated
resolution of moral quandaries. He seeks to establish an account of moral development
defined by reason and revealed through the developmental process. He argues
that moral conflicts are best resolved through principles of justice and that
such reasoning is auto-motivating, sufficient to compel moral action (here
Kohlberg adopts Plato’s two maxims, “virtue is one and its name is justice” and
“to know the good is to do the good”).
But these
assumptions have hardly gone unchallenged: other competing conceptions of the
good besides justice, such as care and community, have been advocated and the
predictability of action on the basis of moral judgment is rather tenuous,
pointing to the “gappiness” of moral life. Furthermore, Kohlberg’s vision of
moral maturity centers on principled moral judgment, an ideal ethical
standpoint requiring abstract impartiality as we separate ourselves from our
own personalities and interests to follow the dictates of universalizable moral
principles—a vision of moral maturity that is rather psychologically barren and
suspect. The philosophical constraints and psychological emphases inherent in
Kohlberg’s model have the inevitable consequence of restriction of perspective,
a conceptual skew that results in a narrow view of moral functioning. Kohlberg
was not entirely blind to the constraints placed on his model by the emphasis
on moral rationality and justice, and he attempted to flesh out his theory in
several ways, at least as much as his theoretical allegiances would allow; but
the model could only be tweaked so far and its core emphasis on cognition and justice
remained.
Other
influential theorists in moral psychology2 have also
implicitly assumed the objectives of modernity and so can be similarly tarred
and feathered for their emphasis on moral rationality and minimal attention to
moral personality, character, and intuition.3 The
alignment of the moral psychology field in general has been skewed by this
pervasive emphasis on moral rationality in its application to interpersonal
functioning. This prevailing emphasis on moral rationality has eclipsed attention
to other aspects of moral functioning and has belied the complexity of the
moral life. The danger of this overemphasis on moral rationality is that it
separates people from their own personalities and risks destroying their
motivation to be moral—a situation that has been labeled moral schizophrenia.4 A
slightly different way to articulate this concern is to note moral psychology’s
preoccupation with the interpersonal aspects of moral functioning (justice,
rights, welfare, care) and its relative neglect of the intrapsychic aspects
that involve the characteristics of the good person and the good life (basic
values, identity, integrity). Flanagan similarly critiques the marginalization
of moral character in philosophy and argues convincingly for a more realistic
conception of moral functioning and moral ideals—one that is psychologically
possible for “creatures like us.” Flanagan does not regard current ethical
frameworks as very useful for informing moral action because they presuppose
psychological functioning that is impossible for ordinary people ever to attain.
Any moral
theory must acknowledge that . . . the projects and commitments of particular
persons give each life whatever meaning it has; and that all persons, even very
impartial ones, are partial to their own projects. It follows that no ethical
conception . . . can reasonably demand a form of impersonality, abstraction, or
impartiality which ignores the constraints laid down by universal psychological
features.5
Thus, we
hear increasingly frequent appeals to enrich the psychological study of moral
development by integrating cognition with personality and character, thereby
providing more holistic understandings of moral functioning and effective means
to foster moral development. It is important to note that these criticisms of
the rationalistic bias of contemporary moral psychology do not negate the
essential role that moral reasoning plays; rather these concerns argue for a
more fullbodied and balanced account of moral functioning that meaningfully includes
moral personality and character.
The new
direction that seems to be evolving in the psychology of moral development is
the study of moral personality and character, an approach that has the
potential to include both the inter- and intrapersonal aspects of moral
functioning as well as encompass the cognitive, affective, and behavioral
components. Similarly, recognition is beginning among moral philosophers of the
need to constrain ethical theories by an empirically informed account of how
people ordinarily understand morality, as well as by the psychological
processes involved in moral functioning.6
What I
advocate, and pursue in my own empirical work, is a twopronged approach to
developing such an integrated account of moral functioning: One approach
examines people’s conceptions of moral functioning and moral excellence,
notions that are embedded in everyday language and common understandings, the
other the psychological functioning of moral exemplars, people who have been
identified as leading lives of moral virtue, integrity, and commitment. These
different empirical strategies should be mutually informative, providing
convergent evidence regarding aspects of moral functioning that are operative in
everyday life and should be incorporated into our theories of moral development
and approaches to moral education and socialization.
Part of
the impetus for examining people’s conceptions of moral excellence is to
address the skew that dominant models of moral psychology have introduced
through various biases and prior assumptions. Philosophical perspectives have
the inherent potential to limit and need to be checked against the empirical
evidence yielded by ordinary understanding and intuition. At this juncture,
moral psychology and education need to be more closely aligned with how people
experience morality day by day than by the tight constraints of philosophical conceptualizations.
My hunch is that a broad survey of conceptions of moral functioning may reveal
some important notions that have been sidelined in contemporary moral
psychology because of the encumbrance of philosophical and methodological
blinders.
This new
direction in moral psychological research is illustrated through the findings
of a recent project in which I examined people’s conceptions of moral
excellence.7 Although most theories of moral development accord minimal attention to
definitions of moral exemplarity, Kohlberg did articulate an explicit vision of
moral maturity—the attainment of dilemma-busting principles of justice—but as
argued before, this view is an impoverished and psychologically barren one because
of its focus on moral rationality. Regardless, there is scant empirical
evidence for the elusive Stage 6 (universal ethical principles).
We need a
more compelling and full-bodied conception of moral excellence. My research on
conceptions of moral excellence entailed a sequence of three studies (using
free-listing, prototypicality-rating, and similarity-sorting procedures) and
was intended to provide a handle on people’s implicit notions and typologies of
morality. Analyses identified two dimensions underlying people’s understanding
of moral maturity: a self–other dimension and an external–internal dimension.
The self–other dimension incorporates some of the dynamics of the notions of dominance
and nurturance (or agency and communion) as fundamental in the understanding of
interpersonal behavior, and illustrates the tension between notions of personal
agency and communion in moral functioning. The external–internal dimension
reflects the tension between external moral standards and a personal
conscience. This implies that moral maturity requires both sensitivity to
shared moral norms and development of autonomous moral values and standards.
Analyses
also identified clusters of attributes (or themes) in people’s understanding of
moral maturity. The principled–idealistic cluster reflects the importance of a
range of strongly held values and principles and the maintenance of high
standards and ideals—an acute and evident sense of morality. The fair cluster
entails the notions of justice, principle, and rationality that reflect
Kohlberg’s conception of moral excellence, so naturalistic conceptions do
include that component of morality. The dependable–loyal and caring–trustworthy
clusters resonate with themes of interpersonal sensitivity and warmth. Thus,
otheroriented compassion and care that entail helpful and considerate action, as
well as the nurturing of relationships through faithfulness and reliability, are
significant in notions of moral functioning. The confident cluster references
the qualities of agency that are important in the pursuit of moral goals. The
strong commitment to moral values and standards (principled–idealistic cluster)
joined with a strong sense of self and agency (confident cluster) may
contribute to the integrity that is viewed as essential to moral maturity (has
integrity cluster)—that the moral person is committed to action based on these
principles, values, and ideals, and has the personal fortitude to do so.
Among the
moral virtues emphasized here were notions of honesty, truthfulness, and
trustworthiness, as well as those of care, compassion, thoughtfulness, and
considerateness. Other salient traits revolve around virtues of dependability,
loyalty, and conscientiousness. These aspects of moral character are
foundational for interpersonal relationships and social functioning, but have
received scant attention in moral psychology or have been relegated to an
immature good-boy-girl mentality. Finally, the notion of integrity is at the
core of the depiction of moral excellence. Integrity represents the connection
between thought and action, but both the rationalistic and behavioral models of
moral functioning have been unable to escape their own parameters and, thus,
the notion of integrity has fallen into the void when instead it should be basic
both to our understanding of moral psychology and attempts to nurture its
development.
This
notion of integrity and the development of a moral self is, however, receiving
increasing attention in moral psychology and moral philosophy.8 Blasi
advocates the notion of a moral self that reflects how people conceptualize the
moral domain and the extent to which morality is salient and significant in
their self-concept and identity. Research with moral exemplars points to the
exceptional merger of self and morality in their lives, with little distinction
between personal and moral goals,9 and with
self-attributions that predominantly include moral personality traits and
goals.10 Also in Blasi’s model are the notions of personal responsibility for
moral action and of self-consistency or integrity. Obviously, moral psychology
requires a systematic empirical examination of the role of the self in moral
functioning, as it has the potential to link the cognitive and emotive aspects
of moral functioning to behavior. An example of such work is Bandura’s research
on the selfregulating affective processes that are sometimes deactivated in the
context of one’s own questionable conduct.11 Given
people’s strong need to regard themselves as moral, Bandura notes the
corrupting power of rationalizations in laundering evaluations of behavior to
preserve this sense of the moral self (through reconstruals, euphemistic
labeling, advantageous comparisons, displacement of responsibility). The
greater self-awareness and self-consistency of moral maturity should help to inhibit
such moral disengagement.
There are
some difficulties with virtue ethics, in general, that need to be kept front
and center as the field moves in this new direction. For example, a listing of
moral virtues, such as was done in this study, represents an amalgamation of
traits that would be impossible, indeed incoherent, for any one person to
embody. At present, we little understand how these aspects of moral character
interact in psychological functioning. Lapsley has noted that not all virtues
are necessarily compatible: “Certain characterological blindspots might be the
price one pays for cultivating excellences in other domains of one’s life.”12 An illustration
in this regard comes from Colby and Damon’s study of moral exemplars who were
identified largely on the basis of their commitment to moral causes (in other
words, most were social activists).13 Many exemplars
expressed regrets regarding relationships with their children who sometimes
seemed to lose out in competition with their parents’ pursuit of social causes.
On a related
theme, it also needs to be recognized that virtues sometimes have maladaptive,
or at least morally questionable, aspects to their expression. Hennig and
Walker used techniques of personality assessment to map the ethic-of-care
domain.14 We focused on aspects of the virtue of care where it has in some sense
gone awry, being dysfunctional for either the carer or the one cared for.
Self-sacrificial care can justify self-neglect and overinvolvement in others’
lives, and thus compromise the quality of care undertaken. Another maladaptive pattern
identified was submissive care, where care for the other is anxiously motivated
by fear of negative evaluation and where one’s selfexpression is inhibited in
deference to others’ opinions. In other words, the virtue of caring can take on
less than authentic manifestations. This is presumably true for most virtues,
and moral psychology would be served well by a careful conceptual and empirical
analysis along these lines of other moral traits.
It should
be obvious that there may be no single viable prototype for moral maturity or
ideal of moral character; indeed, there may be many different types of moral
excellence and moral exemplars. My current research explores conceptions of
different types of moral excellence that may reveal the clusters of virtues
associated with different types as well as reveal the virtues that are seen as
foundational to all manifestations of moral maturity. That there are many
different types of moral exemplars is illustrated by the findings of a study
where participants were asked to identify moral exemplars and to justify their choices.15 A wide
range of moral exemplars was identified, including humanitarians,
revolutionaries, social activists, religious leaders, politicians, and so on.
However, the most frequent categories were family members and friends. Many
participants expressed an explicit distrust of the public persona of historical
figures, preferring to nominate individuals they knew intimately and were
better able to evaluate. There are a couple of notable things here: First, that
a great diversity of moral exemplars was identified; and second, thatmanymoral
exemplars would not be considered well-known. Analysis of the justifications
for these nominations revealed that actual moral exemplars are not typically described
as having a full complement of moral virtues but rather are seen as embodying a
smaller subset (think of Oskar Schindler vs. Martin Luther King vs. Mother
Teresa), suggesting the need for us to understand better the complex
interrelationships among these aspects of moral character and how they are
manifested. Of course, these naturalistic conceptions of moral maturity need to
be checked against analyses of the psychological functioning of actual moral
exemplars. Do real moral paragons actually evidence the range of attributes
derived from natural language concepts? It is to this complementary avenue of research
that we now turn.
Another
way to examine the development of moral character and personality is through
comprehensive analyses of the psychological functioning of people who have been
identified as leading morally exemplary lives. In a landmark study that frames
our own research in some respects, Colby and Damon studied a sample of people
who evidenced extraordinary commitment to moral ideals and causes over an
extended period of time.16 Their
case-study analysis revealed that these exemplars were not particularly
distinguished in terms of principled moral reasoning, again challenging the
dominant prototype for moral maturity, but they were characterized by other
processes suggestive of various aspects of the moral personality, including:
(a) active receptivity to progressive social influence and a continuing
capacity to change, (b) considerable certainty about moral principles and
values which was balanced by relentless truth-seeking and openmindedness
(precluding dogmatism), (c) positivity and optimism, humility (with a disavowal
of moral courage), love for all people, a capacity to forgive, and an
underlying faith or spirituality, and (d) an exceptional uniting of self and
morality, reflecting an identity that fused the personal and moral aspects of
their lives (as noted earlier in the discussion of the moral self). They saw moral
problems in everyday events and saw themselves as implicated in these problems
and responsible to act. Despite these valuable insights, it should be noted
that this was a small, select sample with no comparison group, the method was
assisted autobiographical interview with no standard measures of psychological
functioning, and the analyses were solely qualitative.
The value
of analyses of the psychological functioning of moral exemplars in suggesting
processes underlying the development of moral personality and character can be
further demonstrated through the findings of another recent project, a study
that we believe provides one of the more comprehensive assessments of moral
exemplarity.17 An exemplar group of forty young adults was nominated by social service agencies
because of their extraordinary moral commitment as volunteers, and a matched
comparison group was also recruited. Participants completed several
questionnaires and responded to a lengthy life-narrative interview. In an
attempt to provide a comprehensive assessment of individuals’ psychological
functioning, the choice of measures here reflected McAdams’ typology of three
broad levels of personality assessment: (a) dispositional traits, (b)
contextualized concerns such as developmental tasks and personal strivings, and
(c) integrative narratives of the self.18 In terms
of dispositional traits, participants completed a questionnaire assessing
traits reflecting the five fundamental factors underlying personality. Of the
five factors, agreeableness and conscientiousness are considered the classic
dimensions of character and thus most relevant here. Not surprisingly, the
exemplar group was found to be higher on agreeableness than the comparison
group, confirming that personality dispositions are implicated in moral action.
To assess
the midlevel of contextualized concerns in understanding personality
functioning, we included various measures of developmental tasks and personal
strivings. It was found that, in contrast to the comparison group, the exemplar
group was more mature in their identity, reflecting a stronger commitment to
values and greater stability; they evidenced more mature faith development,
reflecting the process by which they make meaning in life; and they used more
advanced moral reasoning, confirming its critical role in moral functioning.
At the
third level of personality assessment we examined themes in individuals’ life
narratives. Our expectation was that exemplars’ life narratives would by
characterized by more themes of agency and communion than would be evident for
the comparison individuals. Our hunch was partly supported in that more agentic
themes were found in exemplars’ life stories. This finding resonates with the
results of our previous study that identified personal agency as a salient
dimension underlying understandings of moral excellence.19
In
summarizing our research on moral exemplars, we found that variables indicative
of all three levels of personality assessment distinguished exemplars from
comparison individuals (despite matching on demographic variables). Yet, we
need to keep in mind that moral maturity can be exemplified in different ways,
and it is important for our understanding of moral functioning to determine
what is distinctive about different types of moral exemplars as well as the
common core. We currently have research underway along these lines. Once the
field shows some sense of the psychological functioning of moral exemplars, the
research agenda may then focus on the formative factors in the development of
such moral character.
My
premise in this chapter is that progress in moral psychology and moral
education has stalled because of the conceptual skew of the models of moral
development that dominate the field with their focus on moral rationality and
aversion to personological factors, and the resultant psychologically barren
conception of moral functioning. Furthermore, their emphasis has been on the
interpersonal aspects of morality, while ignoring the intrapsychic aspects that
pertain more to our basic values, lifestyle, identity, and character.
The new
direction advocated here is intended as a corrective to this misalignment and
stresses the development of moral personality, character, and virtue, a new
direction that can perhaps best be instanced through the study of moral
exemplarity. This approach has the potential to include both the inter- and
intrapersonal aspects of morality because moral character and virtues are
reflected in our relationships. It also has the potential to integrate the
cognitive, affective, and behavioral components of moral functioning, because
the notion of moral character is not so amenable to this psychological
trichotomy and implicates all in its manifestations. This new direction
resonates with recent appeals for the study of positive human characteristics
and the experiences that foster such behaviors—what is known as the positive
psychology movement. 20
An
initial two-pronged empirical approach to the study of moral exemplarity is
described and illustrated. One approach is to examine conceptions of moral
excellence, rooted in everyday language and common understandings, as an avenue
to a broad understanding of moral virtues and ideals. The other approach is to
examine the actual psychological functioning of individuals identified as moral
exemplars, using the template of the most valid models and measures of human
development. It is anticipated that these two approaches will yield convergent evidence
regarding moral functioning and ideals; their points of divergence will require
some rethinking of our notions. The beginning research along these lines has
implications for our engagement in moral education with our children and youth.
Perhaps pivotal is the need to sensitize children to the breadth of the moral
domain and the moral implications of their values, choices, and actions.
Morality should be considered a pervasive part of everyday life and should be
front-andcenter in our thinking. Making children more aware of the moral domain
will facilitate the development of a moral identity where moral concerns become
relevant to most things undertaken in life.
Moral
education should also entail a critical discussion of moral virtues. Simply
plastering the classroom walls with virtue labels will do little, if anything,
to engender good moral character; rather, children need to appreciate the
complexities and perhaps even the maladaptive aspects of many virtues such as
honesty and care, and to struggle daily with how to exemplify these virtues.
Some illustrations may help to demonstrate my point here regarding the
complexity and shadowy side of many virtues. The virtue of honesty needs to be
tempered by considerations of avoiding hurt to others, as when responding to
grandma’s query about whether you liked the sweater she knit for you (when the sweater
is hopelessly out of style). Likewise, the virtue of care can be maladaptive
when excessive caring for others is based on self-denigration and -denial and
simply results in a resentful sense of obligation in others. Children need to
appreciate that appropriate care depends on maintaining an authentic sense of
self. Other virtues often also come into conflict, and those situations need to
be carefully considered; for example, when loyalty to a friend is challenged by
a teacher’s interrogation about cheating in the classroom. The notion of moral
exemplarity means that such moral examples are worthy of some emulation.
Children
need to explore the lives of a range of moral exemplars. Certainly, some
well-known historical and publicly visible exemplars need to be examined; but
also, the lives of local and personal heroes should be included. Here it is
important that lives in all their fullness are examined, not just heroes’
statements or actions, but rather the complexity of their personalities, the
formative aspects of their experiences, and their weaknesses and struggles. It
is important for children to recognize the diversity in moral exemplarity and
to identify with a personal hero. Children should not simply cognitively study
moral exemplars, but their involvement in moral action should be facilitated. The
recent emphasis on meaningful community service involvement reflects this idea.
Finally,
children need to struggle with underlying tensions in moral functioning, as
were described earlier in our research. For example, one dimension underlying
notions of morality is the self–other dimension that involves the notions of
agency and communion. Here there is a need to balance the development of
competency with interpersonal sensitivity, sometimes a difficult equilibrium to
maintain in many moral situations. The development of children’s commitment to
moral values and their willingness to act on them needs to be balanced by
openness to new ideas and sensitivity to the perspectives and circumstances of others.
The danger is that we can instill such a sense of personal agency and moral
certainty in children that they run roughshod over others in their pursuit of
their own moral goals. Another dimension underlying notions of morality is the
external–internal dimension that reflects the frequent tension between shared
moral norms and autonomous moral principles. Here again, children need to
appreciate the occasional tension between respect for the moral values of one’s
community and the need to follow carefully considered individual moral ideals
and principles. Certainly, there are many possibilities to consider and
evaluate as we chart new directions in moral psychology and moral education.
1. See L.
Kohlberg, Essays on Moral Development, Vol. 1, The Philosophy of Moral Development
(San Francisco: Harper&Row, 1981) and Vol. 2, The Psychology of
Moral Development (San Francisco: Harper
& Row, 1984).
2. N.
Eisenberg, “Prosocial Development: A Multifaceted Model,” in W. M. Kurtines and
J. L. Gewirtz, eds., Moral Development: An
Introduction (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1995); C.
Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982); J. R. Rest, D. Narvaez, M. J. Bebeau,
and S. J. Thoma, Postconventional Moral Thinking: A
Neo-Kohlbergian Approach (Mahwah, N.J.: Erlbaum,
1999); R. A. Shweder, M. Mahapatra, and J. G. Miller, “Culture and Moral
Development, “ in J. Kagan and S. Lamb, eds., The Emergence of Morality
in Young Children (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1987): 1–83; E. Turiel, The Development of Social
Knowledge: Morality and Convention (Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press, 1983).
3. R. L.
Campbell and J. C. Christopher, “Moral Development Theory: A Critique of Its
Kantian Presuppositions,” Developmental Review 16
(1996): 1–47; J. Haidt, “The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social
Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment,” Psychological Review (in
press); D. K. Lapsley, Moral Psychology (Boulder,
Colo.: Westview Press, 1996) and “An Outline of a Social-Cognitive Theory of
Moral Character,” Journal of Research in Education 8 (1998):
25–32.
4. M.
Stocker, “The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories,” Journal
of Philosophy 73 (1976): 453–66.
5. O.
Flanagan, Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1991): 100–101.
6. See
especiallyM. L. Johnson, “How Moral Psychology Changes Moral Theory,” in L.
May, M. Friedman, and A. Clark, eds., Minds and Morals: Essays on
Cognitive Science and Ethics (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press, 1996): 45–68.
7. L. J.
Walker and R. C. Pitts, “Naturalistic Conceptions of Moral Maturity,” Developmental
Psychology 34 (1998): 403–19.
8. A.
Blasi, “Moral Understanding and the Moral Personality:The Process of Moral Integration,”
in W. M. Kurtines and J. L. Gewirtz, eds., Moral Development: An
Introduction (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1995): 229–53; G.
G. Noam and T. E. Wren, eds., The Moral Self (Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); V. A. Punzo, “After Kohlberg: Virtue Ethics and the
Recovery of the Moral Self,” Philosophical Psychology 9 (1996):
7–23; L. J. Walker and K. H. Hennig, “Moral Development in the Broader Context
of Personality,” in S. Hala, ed., The Development of Social
Cognition (East Sussex, England: Psychology Press, 1997): 297–327.
9. A.
Colby and W. Damon, Some Do Care: Contemporary
Lives of Moral Commitment (New York: Free Press,
1992).
10. D.
Hart and S. Fegley, “Prosocial Behavior and Caring in Adolescence: Relations to
Self-Understanding and Social Judgment,” Child Development 66
(1995): 1346–59.
11. A.
Bandura, “Social Cognitive Theory of Moral Thought and Action,” in W. M.
Kurtines and J. L. Gewirtz, eds., Handbook of Moral Behavior
and Development, Vol. 1 (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum,
1991): 45–103.
12. See
Lapsley, 1998: 32.
13. See
Colby and Damon, 1992.
14. K. H.
Hennig and L. J. Walker, Mapping the Care Domain: A
Structural and Substantive Analysis. Manuscript submitted for
publication, University of British Columbia, 2001.
15. L. J.
Walker, R. C. Pitts, K. H. Hennig, and M. K. Matsuba, “Reasoning about Morality
and Real-Life Moral Problems,” in M. Killen and D. Hart, eds., Morality
in Everyday Life: Developmental Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1995): 371–407.
16. See
Colby and Damon, 1992.
17. M. K.
Matsuba and L. J. Walker, Caring for Their Community:
Study of Moral Exemplars in Transition to Adulthood. Manuscript in preparation,
University of British Columbia, 2001.
18. D. P.
McAdams, “What Do We Know When We Know a Person?” Journal of Personality 63
(1995): 365–96.
19. See
Walker and Pitts, 1998.
20. M. E.
P. Seligman and M. Csikszentmihalyi, “Positive Psychology: An Introduction,” American
Psychologist 55(2000): 5–14.
==============================
Nancy
Sherman
In a
remarkably prescient moment, James B. Stockdale, then a senior Navy pilot shot down
over Vietnam, muttered to himself as he parachuted into enemy hands, “Five
years down there, at least. I’m leaving behind the world of technology and
entering the world of Epictetus.”1 Epictetus’s
famous handbook, the Enchiridion, was
Stockdale’s bedtime reading in the many carrier wardrooms he occupied as he
cruised in the waters off Vietnam in the mid-sixties. Stoic philosophy
resonated with Stockdale’s temperament and profession, and he committed many of
Epictetus’s pithy remarks to memory. Little did he know on that shoot-down day
of Septemer 9, 1965, that Stoic tonics would hold the key to his survival for
six years of POW life. They would also form the backbone of his leadership
style as the senior officer in the POW chain of
command.
It
doesn’t take too great a stretch of the imagination to think of a POW survivor
as a kind of Stoic sage, for the challenge the POW lives with is the Stoic’s
challenge: to find dignity when stripped of nearly all nourishment of the body
and soul. Stoicism is a philosophy of defense, a philosophy of “sucking it up.”
On a strict reading, it minimizes vulnerability by denying the intrinsic
goodness of things that lie outside one’s control. In many ways, boot camp is a
green soldier’s early lesson in Stoicism. In general, it is easy to think of
military men and women as Stoics. The very term has come to mean, in our
vernacular, controlled, disciplined, not easily agitated or disturbed. Military
officers tend to cultivate these character traits. In a vivid way, they live
out the consolations of Stoic practical philosophy. In this paper I explore
certain aspects of military moral education by returning to ancient Stoic
teachings. My own tour of duty with the military began on a drizzly February day
in 1994. A Navy chaplain had invited me to brainstorm with the top brass about
moral remediation for some 133 midshipmen implicated in an “EE” or “double E”
(electrical engineering) cheating scandal.
The
chaplain knew I was no Navy insider, but he wanted my input as an academic
ethicist. That February meeting in 1994 led initially to a consultancy and
visiting ethics lectureship whose audience was the implicated EE students.
Then, in 1997, I was appointed the inaugural Distinguished Chair in Ethics at
the Naval Academy. I was brought aboard, in naval lingo, to teach what American
and European universities had been teaching for the better part of this
century—essentially, Ethics 101. But at an engineering school like the Naval
Academy, introductory ethics had passed them by. Leadership courses were a standard
mix of management and motivational psychology. Yet the far more ancient subject
of ethics was somehow viewed as a newfangled, possibly heretical course that
would dare to teach what ought to be bred in the bones. I was to teach ethics,
ethics for the military. That was contractual. What wasn’t prearranged was what
the military would teach me. They would allow me entrance into a world that for
many of my generation had been cut off by Vietnam and had remained largely impregnable
ever since. And they would offer something of a living example of the doctrines
of Stoicism I had studied before only as texts. The allure of Stoicism became
explicit each term at a certain point in the semester. The course I taught
covered topical themes of honesty, liberty, virtue, and just war interwoven
with the writings of historical figures such as Aristotle and Aquinas, John
Stuart Mill and Immanuel Kant, and Epictetus as a representative Stoic. It was
when we arrived at Epictetus that many felt they had come home. What resonated
with them was what resonated with Jim Stockdale as he read Epictetus each night.
There are
things which are within our power, and there are things which are beyond our
power. Within our power are opinion, aim, desire, aversion, and in one word,
whatever affairs are our own. Beyond our power are body, property, reputation,
office, and in one word, whatever are not properly our own affairs.
. . .
Remember, then, that if you attribute freedom to things by nature dependent and
take what belongs to others for your own, you will be hindered, you will
lament, you will be disturbed, you will find fault both with gods and men . . .
If it concerns anything beyond our power, be prepared to say that it is nothing
to you.2
Epictetus
rightly thinks that our opinions, desires, and emotions are in our power, not
in the radical sense that we can produce them, instantly, at will, but in the
sense that we can do things, indirectly, to shape them. He is right to think,
with the Stoics in general, that our opinions about self and others influence
our desires and emotions. In contrast to these things over which we have some
control, we have far less control over other sorts of goods. A marine may be
killed in friendly fire that he had no way of avoiding, a sailor may be
deserving of decoration and promotion, though overlooked because of gender
prejudice that she alone can’t change, stocks may take a nosedive however
prudent one’s investments. A Stoic, like Epictetus, reminds us of the line that
divides what is and what is not within our control and that we will be miserable
if our happiness itself depends too heavily upon things over which we have
little dominion. The Stoic recommendation is not complacency or a retreat to a
narrow circle of safety. We are to continue to meet challenges and take risks,
to stretch the limits of our mastery. We are to continue to strive with our
best efforts to achieve our ends, but we must learn greater strength in the
face of what we simply cannot change.
Who are
the Stoics from whom the military take implicit guidance? Epictetus has been
mentioned, but we need to put his writings in historical context. Roughly
speaking, the ancient Stoics span the period from 300 b.c. to a.d. 200. They
are part of the broad Hellenistic movement of philosophy that follows upon
Aristotle and includes, in addition to Stoicism, ancient Skepticism and
Epicureanism. The early Greek Stoics, known as the old Stoa (taking their name
from the stoa or painted colonnade near the central piazza
of Athens where disciples paced back and forth) were interested in systematic
philosophical thought that joined ethics with studies in physics and logic. The
works of the founders of the school—Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus—survive
only in fragments, quoted by later writers. Indeed, much of what we know about Stoicism
comes through Roman redactors such as Cicero, Seneca, Epictetus, and Marcus
Aurelius. These Roman redactors, some writing in Greek—Epictetus and Marcus
Aurelius—others writing in Latin—Seneca and Cicero—viewed themselves as public
philosophers at the center of public life.
Cicero
(106–43 b.c.), well-known Roman political orator, consul, and ally to Pompey, turned
to specifically philosophical writing at the end of his political career after
Caesar’s assassination (which Cicero viewed as a tyrannicide) and while in
hiding from his own future assassins, Antony and the other triumvirs. Though
himself not a Stoic (rather he identified as a member of the New Academy or
school of Skepticism), he wrote extensively on Stoic views and his work,
especially On Ends and On Duties,
remained highly influential throughout the Renaissance and Enlightenment as
statements of Stoic positions. Seneca, writing in the mid-first century a.d., was the
tutor and political adviser of the young emperor, Nero. He wrote voluminously
on, among other things, the passions and how anger, hatred, and envy, if not understood
and properly reined in, can ruin a ruler and bring down a commonwealth, as well
as about attachment and fortune, and how we can learn to become less vulnerable
to their vicissitudes. Epictetus, a Greek slave-turned-philosopher who also
wrote in the time of Nero’s reign, greatly influenced Marcus Aurelius.
Epictetus’s aphoristic writings, summarized in a popular handbook, teach about
the power of our minds and imagination to find a measure of mastery and
fulfillment even in enslavement.
Marcus
Aurelius, a Roman emperor and warrior, wrote his famous Meditations
in a.d. 172 in the fleeting moments of quiet he was able to snatch during German
campaigns. In contrast to Seneca’s writings, which are often addressed to
others, Marcus’s meditations are exhortations to himself, about his status as a
citizen of the world and the community of humanity and god linked through
reason and law with nature. He warns how one can be lured away from reason by
the attractions of place or wealth or pleasurable indulgence, and how a zeal for
glory can pervert happiness. A repeated theme is that we live in a Heraclitean
world of flux. To find happiness, we cannot hold on too tightly to what is
transient and beyond our control.
The
Stoics teach self-sufficiency and the importance of detaching from dependence
on worldly goods that make us vulnerable. In a similar fashion, they advocate
detachment from sticky emotions that mark our investment in things beyond our
control. In a manner of speaking, the soldier preparing for battle heeds that
advice. A Navy flier with whom I taught at the academy once told me that before
he went on a mission, he took control of his emotions by uttering the mantra
“compartmentalize, compartmentalize, compartmentalize.” The trick, of course,
is to know when to compartmentalize and when not to. Mission-preparedness seems
to require it. But full Stoic detachment from emotions that record connection
as well as loss can be too high a price to pay, even for the warrior. In
particular, the capacity to grieve, to mourn one’s dead, is crucial for warrior
survival. Consider Coriolanus, the legendary fifth-century b.c. warrior
who turns against his native city for banishing him. He is portrayed by
Shakespeare as the paragon Stoic warrior. Physically strong and detached, more
at home in the battlefield than with his wife and son, he is the military man
par excellence. Fearless, he sheds few tears. And yet the play’s turning point
comes when Coriolanus remembers how to weep. “It is no little thing,” he
concedes, “to make mine eyes to sweat compassion.” It is Coriolanus’s mother,
Volumnia, who reawakens his soul. Her entreaties persuade him to quit his siege
of Rome and to restore peace. In weeping, Coriolanus finds human dignity.
Coriolanus
may be a loner, a mama’s boy at heart, touched only by a mother’s tears. But
for most soldiers, combat itself nurtures a camaraderie akin to the family
relationships of childhood. The friendship of Achilles and Patroclus, central
to the Iliad, symbolizes brothers-in-arms for all
time.Wecan’t begin to understand Achilles’ near suicidal mourning for Patroclus
without appreciating the sheer intensity of that bond. Moreover, we’re misled
if we think, as many readers have, that a friendship so passionate must be
sexual, that only warrior-lovers could grieve as Achilles does for Patroclus.3 Whether
sexual partners or not, Achilles’ grief for Patroclus could not be greater. The
Iliad, like much of Greek culture, celebrates philia, the
bond of friendship, with all its passion and shared journeys and recognizes the
dignity of grief that comes when death or separation breaks the bond.
In
contemporary war, too, where soldiers put themselves at risk to defend each
other, where Marines risk the living to save the dead or those with little
breath left, the camaraderie of brothers- and sisters-in-arms tempers the
sacrifices. Contemporary combat soldiers don’t always have time to grieve. In
missions where combat rarely stops, where pilots catapult from carriers only
seconds after learning that the sorties before them will never return, where
veterans come home in ones and twos aboard commercial airlines (as they did
from Vietnam) and not en masse with their cohorts (as my father did from World
War II aboard the converted Queen Mary), there is little time or place to sweat
tears of compassion, yet deferring grief has devastating psychological costs. The
issues are raised penetratingly by Jonathan Shay in Achilles
in Vietnam. As a Vietnam veterans’ psychiatrist, he urges that communal grief work
must again take place, as it did in the ancient world of the Iliad, if we
are to help soldiers avoid the living death of postcombat trauma. Many of his
patients say, “I died in Vietnam.” Like Achilles at the death of Patroclus,
they view themselves as already dead, dead and deadened by losing a close
friend, “another self,” as Aristotle would say.
Of
course, the orthodox Stoic might say loss is not real loss if it falls outside
what we can control through our own effort and virtue. We’d do better to change
our habits of attachment than to pamper those whose false attachments create
their losses. But we can learn from Stoicism without embracing its strict
letter. What we can learn is that in the midst of our grieving,we still have a
home in the world, connected to others whose fellowship and empathy support us,
that we have inner resources that allow us to stand again after we have fallen.
This human side of Stoicism can toughen us without robbing us of our humanity.
I am reminded here of a stony-faced Marine colonel, who confided in me one
evening that his most wrenching experience in war came not on the battlefield
but in leaving behind his firstborn, a one-and-a-half year-old boy. Going down
to the plane, to begin his unaccompanied mission, his guts seized up on him. “I
literally became sick to my stomach and vomited the whole way. I was violently
ill the whole flight.” Another colleague told me that flying planes was easy.
He said he was even amazed that he was paid to do what he loved. What was agony
was leaving his wife and child behind. Nothing made that easier. Nothing could.
These are tough warriors, Stoic warriors, but they are made of human stuff.
They sweat tears of compassion. They heave their guts out when they leave their
loved ones.
Other
traditions, before and after Stoicism, present a philosophy with softer, human
lines from the start. So Aristotle emphasizes throughout his ethical and political
writings that the attachments of friendship are an irreducible part of a good
life, and to lose a beloved friend is to lose part of what counts for
happiness. One’s own goodness cannot make up the difference, but necessarily
relies on the goodness of others for completion. Similarly, Judeo-Christian
traditions emphasize the healing power of love and compassion. In Exodus 15.26,
God is portrayed as fearful and awesome, but also for the first time in the
biblical narrative as a healer, ready to protect the Israelites against disease
and provide them with water and bread in their forty-days-and-forty-nights trek
through the wilderness.
The
Stoics may struggle to capture the full palette of emotional attachment, but
they profoundly recognize our cosmopolitan status in the world and stress, in a
way significant for military education, the respect and empathy required of
citizens of the world. Seneca in On Anger reminds
his interlocutor, Novatus, that he is a citizen, not just of his country, but
of that greater city of his, that universal commonwealth of the cosmos.4 Each of
us is a world citizen, the Stoics emphasize, following Diogenes the Cynic’s
notion of the human as a kosmopoliteˆs, literally,
“cosmic, universal citizen.”5 We are
each parts of an extended commonwealth and risk our individual integrity when
we sever ourselves from the fellowship of that community. Marcus Aurelius makes
the point graphically in terms of a much-used Stoic metaphor of the organic
body:
If you
have ever seen a dismembered hand or foot or head cut off, lying somewhere
apart from the rest of the trunk, you have an image of what a man makes of
himself . . . when he . . . cuts himself off and does some unneighborly act . .
. For you came into the world as a part and you have cut yourself off.6
Thus, on
the Stoic view, it is as if we mutilate ourselves when we cut ourselves off
from the global community. The notion of extended world citizenship became
relevant to my Navy students as they prepared to risk their lives in foreign
corners of the world and serve in multinational coalitions. Many students
actively wrestled with what they saw as competing views of allegiance—to one’s
country and its leaders and to one’s allies and their leaders. I recall one
student who questioned whether he was really obligated to take orders from
foreign commanders who might head integrated units to which he found himself
assigned. His ultimate loyalty, he insisted, was to the Constitution of the
United States, and after that, through a chain of command from the commander-in-chief
to American commanders. In swearing to uphold the American Constitution he had
not explicitly sworn to serve NATO or other international coalitions or
agreements. This student wasn’t alone in his skepticism. Many midshipmen, on
their initiation day as plebes, have only the faintest idea that in swearing to
uphold the Constitution they are pledging to a broader kind of world
citizenship. The most compelling rebuttal to their skepticism often came from
officers at the Academy who had themselves served in foreign coalitions as part
of their military duty in the Persian Gulf and Bosnia. Many were engaged in
training other nationals for more cohesive membership in coalitions.
Most
understood implicitly that patriotism to country is not undermined by broader
community allegiances. One can be fervently loyal to country and still serve
under or command foreign officers who are part of broader international
coalitions. Marcus Aurelius commanding troops and writing his memoirs today would
most likely guard against a patriotism that demands narrow nationalism. For a
nation and its military to sever itself from the larger alliance of nations
would be an act of selfmutilation, a dismemberment of hand or foot from the
whole body.
The Stoic
Hierocles, writing in the first century a.d., adverts
to the notion of cosmopolitanism as follows: “Each one of us [is] entirely encompassed
by many circles, some smaller, others larger . . . The first circle contains
parents, siblings, wife, and children.” As we move outward, we move through
grandparents, to neighbors, to fellow tribesmen and citizens, and ultimately to
the whole human race. He insists that it is incumbent upon each of us “to draw
the circles together somehow towards the center,” to respect people from the
outer circles as though they were from the inner. We are to do this “by
zealously transferring those from the enclosing circles to the enclosed ones,”
to bring what is far to what is near, “to reduce the distance of the
relationship with each person.”7
Hierocles
himself neither tells us exactly how we are to psychologically assimilate those
in outer circles with inner ones so that we can come to identify with their
circumstances, nor does he explore the nature of our duties, military or otherwise,
in terms of which we show respect for others as we move outward in those
circles. Later philosophers, themselves influenced by the Stoics, fill in the
psychological story. We can do no better than turn to Adam Smith, the
eighteenthcentury Scottish Enlightenment writer. Sympathy, Smith argues, is a cognitive
transport, a cognitive moment of becoming another. In his apt words, it
involves “trading places in fancy,” requiring an active transference of the
mind onto another, a simulation or role-play of what it is like to be another
in his or her circumstances. “To beat time” to another’s breast, he says,
requires a projective capacity by which we imagine another’s case:
As we
have no immediate experience of what other men feel, we can form no idea of the
manner in which they are affected, but by conceiving of what we ourselves
should feel in the like situation. Though our brother is upon the rack, as long
as we ourselves are at our ease our senses will never inform us of what he
suffers. They never did, and never can, carry us beyond our own person, and it
is by the imagination only that we can form any conception of what are his sensations.
. . . It is the impressions of our own senses only, not those of his, which our
imaginations copy. By the imagination we place ourselves in his situation, we
conceive ourselves enduring all the same torments, we enter, as it were, into
his body and become in some measure the same person with him; and thence form
some idea of his sensations, and even feel something which, though weaker in
degree, is not altogether unlike them.8
The
description brilliantly presages what contemporary philosophers of mind and
cognitive psychologists now refer to as a “simulation” process by which we come
to identify with others and, in some sense, “read” their minds. But again, we
do well if we not only go forward in time, but backward. Smith was an avid
reader of Cicero (as were most philosophers of the enlightenment period), and
the notion of “placing ourselves in another’s situation” becomes far clearer if
we bring to bear Cicero’s notion, in On Duties, of the
different personae we wear.9 To read
another’s mind one must “recenter” oneself on another, by imagining, as Cicero
would put it, the shared personae we all have as rational human beings, but
also the personae we wear that are different from person to person. To
empathize with or simply understand others, we must imagine what it is like to
be another with distinctive temperaments and talents, in another’s situation
and circumstances, living life with life choices. It is not just that we
“change” circumstances; we also change who we are in those circumstances. Thus,
we don’t simply put ourselves in others’ shoes. We imagine ourselves as others
in their own shoes. Sometimes we do this
almost unconsciously. But at other times, as Hierocles says, we must keep
zealously working at the transference. We don’t tend to think of the
contemporary warrior as a “cosmopolitan” of this sort, but this is a central
part of ancient Stoic teaching, and one that current-day warriors need to
embrace as they increasingly face the demands of international coalitions and
long-term peacekeeping missions in foreign countries. It is a notion we all
need to take to heart as the demands of global citizenship become more and more
a reality.
Stoicism
within the military revives another ancient Greek educational theme—the belief
that strong bodies and minds must be cultivated together. Even in leg irons,
with a broken leg and in solitary prison, Jim Stockdale forced himself to do
more than a hundred sit-ups each morning. Controlling his own body, in the face
of relentless torture and deprivation, was his way of staying alive and sane.
He lived and breathed the Stoic doctrine that effort, endurance, and inner
virtue are major components of human goodness. Self-endurance began with
gaining control back of his own body, even in shackles.
For a
public obsessed with consumption and consumer products, hungry for epicurean
novelties but tired of pleats of adipose, the stripped-down life of military
endurance and discipline offers an attractive tonic. Whether at eighteen or
fifty, the military officer makes physical discipline part of the daily
regimen. It shows up in the unmistakable, steel-gripped handshake, in workout
regimens that begin or end each day, in physical training tests and weigh-ins
that are part of a military record. All of my students participated in sports
at the end of each class day, and most had additional workout regimens. The
retired officers I worked with closely kept up their training, sporting
youthful bodies well into their late sixties. My office suite mate, retired
Adm. “Bud” Edney, a former pilot and commander in chief (CINC) of the North
Atlantic region, became an avid spinner with his wife in his retirement years, and
kept up with his biking and skiing as family activities. Adm. Larson, the
four-star superintendent of the Naval Academy during my term, had a workout
schedule in his home that began each day before 6 a.m. Others,
who were once submariners and consigned to a treadmill on board, vowed now only
to run outdoors, however inclement the weather. For the military, strong bodies
are mission-critical. The military trains warriors to have the strength to
endure on the battlefield and the stamina to test human limits. Marine boot
camp epitomizes the goal. The eleven-week moral and physical training
culminates with what is called the crucible, two days of sleep and food
deprivation, followed by an obstacle course in grueling environmental
conditions. Survival is group survival. The goal is for the team to return as a
team, even if it means coming home on the back of another.
As
civilians, how should we view physical fitness when strong bodies are not
exactly mission-critical, when there aren’t jungles to pass through, daily
thirty-mile hikes to endure, ammunition, persons, and bodies to carry to
safety? In most white-collar professions, fit bodies are simply not part of the
job description—legs of steel and arms of iron are neither here nor there.
True, how we look in our clothes might subtly matter for job success, but there
is nothing like the ubiquitous (if unwritten) military requirement to look good
in a uniform.
This
misses the obvious point. Civilian fitness is mission-critical
in the very sense that any sort of healthy living requires it. Current worries about
the significant rise of child and adult obesity are not misplaced. We need
weight that doesn’t overly tax vital organs, a strong heart to pump enough oxygen,
adequate release of endorphins, serotonin, and other hormones to give us
vitality and zest, bones that are dense enough to bear our own weight, and so
on.
Ancient
Greek and Roman thought is again an important source of guidance. For Plato and
Aristotle, the great Greek philosophers who preceded the Stoics, virtue is as
much a disposition toward self as toward others, and care of self includes how
we care for our bodies. Temperance, for Aristotle, is a kind of internalized
control in which we no longer have excessive bodily appetites and can moderate
ourselves without much internal conflict. In short, we master indulgence and
its impulses—lose the temptation, as one might say, to do otherwise. The prior
developmental step is egkrateia,
self-control or continence. Here we master appetite, but not without active
struggle and forbearance. When we lapse from either of these forms of control,
we are akratic, literally lacking in control or
weak-willed. Appetite gets the better of judgment when we know what is best,
but act against our knowledge. Weavert our eyes. At times, Aristotle (and
before him, Socrates) suggests that weakness of will is a kind of ignorance.10 But we do
best to think of it as motivated ignorance.
We are ignorant only in the sense that we don’t want to be reminded of what we
know to be best.
Plato’s
dialogue, The Republic, has long influenced
Western culture in its advocacy of an early education that includes gymnastics
as well as music. But Plato insists that in the best education “the exercises
and toils of gymnastics” are not mere “means to muscle;”11 like
music, bodybuilding is a way of shaping the psyche as well. It is a way of
building mental discipline and spiritedness, a way of storing the general habit
and procedures of control in mind as well as in muscle memory. The lessons of
athletics are wasted, Plato insists, if their point is only to make a body more
chiseled or agile. I have heard similar remarks from college athletic coaches
who encourage young people to go into sports, not simply to become athletes,
but to become individuals who have internalized the rigors of discipline and
self-control. As Cicero remarks, strength of soul resembles “the strength and
sinews and effectiveness of the body.”12
In the
contemporary world of the military, temperance and bodily fitness are monitored
by external judges who test and keep records, who have the power to remove a
sailor or marine if there is a lapse. Some of that surveillance can be harsh
and, at times, insensitive to personal and gender differences. Women’s bodies,
by nature more fat-rich than men’s, pose difficult challenges for the military
in measuring body fat. Shortly after I left the Naval Academy, a woman who was
an exemplary student and recipient of a prestigious prize for an ethics essay
was eventually dismissed from the Academy on the grounds that her body fat
exceeded the appropriate standard for her height. Even if the charts are
different for men and women, the danger in a male culture, especially one that
so prizes uniformity and cohesion, is that women will be shoehorned into male
molds. For years, the military struggled with what sort of physical fitness
requirements to impose on women, given women’s different centers of gravity and
strength. Standards now in place reflect reasonable gender differences, but
resentment still lingers among some men that women are getting off the hook too
easily. The reply to these complaints, as one of my colleagues at the Naval
Academy once said, is easy. Ask the guy who objects to the women’s standards if
he would like his acceptable weight range pegged to the women’s charts. Silence
usually ensues.
In the
civilian world, physical fitness and bodily health are more a matter of private
virtue. Doctors have always taken records of weight and height and, in recent
years, increasingly discuss smoking, diet, exercise, and alcohol consumption
with patients. Their influence is typically at the level of recommendation
rather than requirement. By and large, the disciplined care of one’s body sits
squarely on one’s own shoulders. Like most provinces of morality that fall
outside legal purview, it is one’s own business. This is as it should be. And
yet with one out of two Americans overweight, the virtue of temperance seems to
have become a personal virtue that is viewed as optional. “Self-indulgence is a
human condition,” Seneca writes, “even if in some pleasures wild animals are
more intemperate than humans.”13 As with
most virtues, temperance corrects a standing human condition, in this case, the
tendency toward excessive appetite on the one hand, or bodily neglect on the
other. We might add, temperance also corrects overcontrol. If the Stoics are to
offer inspiration, then the lesson to celebrate is not human control in excess,
but in moderation. The Stoics constantly remind us how and in what way we have
more dominion than we might at first think, whether it be in the physical
sphere, moral, or emotional arena. But no plausible Stoicism can urge that we
have unlimited dominion, even over our own virtue.
Strong
characters and bodies are part of the military appeal, but so are manners. For
those who believe manners build morals, the military offers the lesson in
spades. At the mealtime formation at the Academy, visitors line up daily to see
a brigade of crisply pressed uniforms and taut, straight bodies. Officers and
midshipmen generally greet civilians with a “sir” or “ma’am,” locked eye gaze,
and firm handshake. They are helpful and courteous, polite and civil. The
question that came to nag me as an ethicist was “how deep does surface conduct
go?” Do manners lead to morals, etiquette to ethics? Should the civilian world,
baffled by the degeneration of civility in public life, take better notice of
the role of decorum in military culture? Is good conduct a part of good
character? It is easy to be skeptical here. Codes of conduct are highly local. What
one group finds a pleasing sign of respect, another may find overly formal or
off-putting. Given the variability of conduct codes across cultures, how can
behavior that is so culture-specific get to the heart of what matters morally?
Moreover, much military conduct is mindless drill and compliance motivated by
fear of those higher up in the chain of command. Can motivation so pegged to
punishment still help an individual achieve inner virtue?
These
legitimate concerns are not easily dismissed. They are criticisms most
civilians would bring to a military environment, myself included. Yet I have
become persuaded that the military is right in thinking that manners matter.
Like moral acts such as helping or rescuing, showing courage or generosity,
moral manners are also ways we routinely express our concern or respect for
others. To look another in the eye but not stare them down, to listen without
interrupting, to be mindful of what would offend, insult, or shame are in many
cultures simply ways to acknowledge others as worthy of respect. True, certain manners
may have more local coinage than others, but the fact that codes of etiquette
vary culturally and that some codes are morally problematic does not generally
impugn the connection of a good code of etiquette with morality.14
Stoic
teachings are again instructive here. Seneca writes a lengthy, seven-book
treatise on the subject of how to give and receive favors. It is a subject we
might think, at first blush, befitting only the interests of Miss Manners and
her readership. But as we read “On Favours,” Seneca shows us how the matter is
central to morality and crucial for human fellowship. Even a Stoic, bent on
hardscrabble integrity and self-reliance, has an obligation to give and take
gifts with grace: “When we have decided to accept [a gift], we should do so
cheerfully.Weshould express our delight and make it obvious to our benefactor.
We must show our gratitude by pouring out our feelings and bearing witness to
them, not only in his presence but everywhere.”15 These
attitudes are part of how we care for others and show our gratitude when cared
for. Similarly, in On Duties, Cicero
limns in considerable detail how “our standing, our walking, our sitting and
our reclining, our countenances, our eyes and the movements of our hands” all
are the outward expressions of our character.16 Moreover,
the Stoics hold that moral virtue requires a progression that moves from doing
actions because they are appropriate and externally in accord with rules of
right action, to doing actions that are right because they are motivated by
virtue itself. What is mere good conduct in one person can in another be a
morally worthy action because of its motivation.
Even if
we grant the contribution of good manners to good morals, we might still doubt
whether the military is the right model to watch. Consider Robert Duvall,
playing the role of career officer in the movie The Great
Santini. He painfully discovers that he can be the military colonel at home to
his wife and children only at risk of losing them. He takes the gamble, for he
knows no other way of winning respect. (Similarly, one midshipman toldmeafter
returning from Thanksgiving break that he was confused at home as to how to
address his parents. Should he call them, “Sir” or “Ma’am” as he does his
commanding officers, or just “Mom”and Dad” as he always has? The appropriate
forms of respect had become fuzzy in his mind.)
Santini’s
notion of respect is based on hierarchy and rank as captured by the idea that a
military person salutes the uniform, not the person, and the uniform higher up
in the chain of command. (The sight is a common one at the Naval Academy as
students with almost mechanically hinged forearms salute officers whom they
pass in the yard.) Outside the military, respect is a more democratic notion.
Parents and elders may deserve special honor, but all, simply as persons, are worthy
of basic respect. Moreover, respect in the civilian world is often conveyed in
caring about the feelings of others, that one not shame, humiliate, or slight
insofar as such attitudes offend a person’s dignity. This is certainly an
underlying theme in Seneca’s treatise, “On Favours,” but it is the rare
commander who is terribly worried about the nuances of hurt feelings or
squashed egos. Most officers would contend that a goodly amount of ego
deflation is requisite for strong unit cohesion and achievement of the mission.
Finally, there’s the nagging issue of appearance, so critical to the military. Appearing
respectful matters. Yet, why put so much emphasis on the pretense and
artifice of behavior? Why reward the person who may be only a hypocrite or
dissembler? Moreover, how does a straight back or hair pinned impeccably in
place actually reflect on the goodness of a soul? In the ladies’ room at the Academy,
I saw women fix each strand of hair in place with bobby pins and spray so that
not a wisp fell below regulation shoulder length. They clearly cared about the
well-groomed look of an officer.
What
underlies such care for decorum other than the desire to please? Both Cicero
and Seneca argue that much decorum is underpinned by a desire to please and to
take others’ opinions into account.17 They
don’t explicitly defend the stance, but imply that some degree of concern for
how one is viewed is intimately connected with respect for others. Desiring to
be agreeable, not to offend or disdain, not to slight, is part of what is
involved in taking another seriously.Weoughtn’t make ourselves servile in the
task or violate our own views of what is morally right in order not to offend.
In cases where there is no conflict, concern for another at the level of
emotional and formal comportment seems a part of moral respect for them. For
this reason manners matter. Even Immanuel Kant, the eighteenth-century German
Enlightenment philosopher, notorious for his austere Stoic-inspired philosophy of
duty, urges that duty is not just inner virtue but a matter of manner and
affect as well:
No matter
how insignificant these laws of refined humanity may seem, especially in
comparison with pure moral laws, anything that promotes sociability, even if it
consists only in pleasing maxims or manners, is a garment that dresses virtue
to advantage, a garment to be recommended to virtue in more serious respects
too.18
It is
often said that anger is the underbelly of courage, that it mobilizes us to
fight, that we need to keep the flame of anger kindled to be warriors. Cicero
rehearses the view: “no stern commands” can rally ourselves or others, whether
on the battlefield or off, “without something of the keen edge of
irascibility.” Irascibility is “the whetstone of bravery.”19 Both Cicero
and Seneca deny the claim. Indeed, the Stoics argue strenuously that anger and
rage are pernicious emotions that do more damage than good. “No plague has cost
the human race more,” Seneca says in his famous treatise, “On Anger.” A true
Stoic warrior doesn’t rely on anger to fight his battles.
Part of
the problem with anger, according to the Stoics, is that it can’t easily be
moderated—once turned on, it can’t easily be turned off. It is a runaway
passion, the Stoics say, whose stride outpaces the command of reason. It is
“the most rabid and unbridled of all emotions,”20 says
Seneca. It perverts the body and mind, and literally disfigures the face.
Seneca is graphic in his portrait. Those who are angry have
eyes
ablaze and glittering, a deep flush over all the face as blood boils up from
the vitals, quivering lips, teeth pressed together, bristling hair standing on
end, breath drawn in and hissing, the crackle of writhing limbs, groans and
bellowing . . . . thehideous horrifying face of swollen self-degradation—you
would hardly know whether to call the vice hateful or ugly.21
Seneca
insists that we can control this hideous frenzy and rid ourselves of its
corrosive effects by a bold straightforward method: let go of the kinds of
attachments to honor or reputation, or victory or wealth, which when threatened
make us angry. These are not real goods, he teaches, following ancient Stoic
doctrine. True, the Stoics concede, they are the kinds of goods that we might
like to have and that we prefer rather than not prefer, but having them adds
nothing substantive to our happiness. They are not genuine parts of happiness
which in the Stoic view (which closely follows Socrates’ teachings) is only a
function of inner virtue. Its prosperity is the prosperity of virtue, not of
wealth, fortune, or the opinions of others.
The full
Stoic view may be hard to swallow. We do depend on others’ opinions of us, and
think our reputation in a community matters. We would be different creatures,
far less social and communal, far less able to achieve the very Stoic goals of
community and fellowship, if we were indifferent to others’ praise and blame,
compliments or slights. We couldn’t raise children without praise and blame
from parents. Yet, in holding that certain emotions, like anger, involve
mistaken values, the Stoics presuppose something more fundamental and more
revealing, namely, that emotions are themselves evaluations or appraisals, ways
of judging the world. Aristotle holds that emotions involve construals about
the world, though on his position those construals are neither systematically
false nor misleading.22 They are part and parcel of
knowing the world accurately and wisely—a view that has been reappropriated by
contemporary cognitive psychologists. In that view, emotions involve cognitive
assessments of the environment that lead to arousal and desiderative responses.
So sadness involves an appraisal that I have been hurt, love the idea that he
is attractive, or pity the thought that someone has suffered unjustly. The
Stoics go whole hog, though, in holding that emotions are nothing but beliefs,
and consequently, that we can change emotions in their entirety by changing
beliefs. There is no remainder. We might say they are the first to advocate a
thoroughgoing cognitive therapy as a method of emotional change. Under their aegis,
the particular form that cognitive therapy takes is philosophical dialectic.
“Row the oars of dialectic,” Cicero says, if you are to transform the soul.23
Few of us
hold with the Stoics that emotions are nothing but beliefs or as corrigible as
them. Nor are we likely to endorse the Stoic doctrine that the kind of beliefs
emotions involve predominantly embody false values. Rather, most of us probably
think, with Aristotle and current cognitive psychologists, that emotions often
give us truthful views of the world, even if sometimes exaggerated or
magnified. We also tend to think that the desires that lace emotions and the
physiological arousals expressive of emotions make for states that are as much
body as mind and hence hard to relinquish by a sheer act of will. Few of us are
ready to embrace wholeheartedly the Stoic doctrine that all goods other than the
pure goodness of our souls ought to be matters of complete indifference to us,
things from which we can fully detach in a search for a meaningful life. Yet
despite the harshness of some of their views, the Stoics propound a view that
we are likely to have considerable sympathy with, and this is that to some
degree, emotions embody ways of thinking about the world and evaluating it.
Emotions judge the world, and when we subtly shift those ways of thinking
(i.e., stop thinking that something is an offense, loss, injury, or
attraction), we shift our emotional states.
What most
of us probably dispute is that the cognitive shift is itself sufficient for an
emotional shift, that feeling can be reduced to believing. We now need to
return to the original specific Stoic claim that anger is an emotion needing
extirpation. Can a Stoic, who roots out all anger, be trained to kill? Does
this feature of a Stoic education make sense for a military person? I would
suggest the harder conceptual problem is not in considering the possibility
that a warrior lacks anger, but that a virtuous person is devoid of all anger.
To be a soldier, defending principle, abiding by rules of engagement, cognizant
of the constraints of just war and just conduct in war embodied in such
documents as the Law of Land warfare or the Geneva Conventions, in fact, requires
a principled response to the demands of warfare. To act out of frenzy or rage,
to systematically dehumanize the enemy in the way that anger toward an enemy
often requires, for a commander to incite his troops by bloody thirst for
revenge, for a pilot to be battle-happy in a way that makes him nonchalant
about the no-fly zone, is to risk running afoul of the moral framework of war.
No one can fight without the adrenaline rush of aggression and competitive
spirit, and it is a drill sergeant’s job to push his troops to know those
emotions well. But that physiological arousal may not itself be underpinned by
the kinds of judgments that Seneca claims underlie irascibility and rage.
Even if
we can conceive of a warrior who fights best because of principle rather than
anger, can we conceive of a virtuous person who leaves behind his senses of
anger, moral indignation, and outrage?
Consider
retired Chief Warrant Officer Hugh Thompson, the man some have called the hero
of My Lai.24 On March 16, 1968, he was flying his observation helicopter when he
spotted several wounded people on the ground and a dike where a group of GIs
approached an injured, unarmed woman of about twenty. Later one officer prodded
the woman with his foot, then killed her. Minutes later Thompson saw dozens of bodies
in an irrigation ditch, their writhing movements suggesting that some were
still alive. American infantrymen beside the ditch were taking a cigarette
break from battle, taking off their steel helmets for a moment of respite.
Several minutes later, he saw one of the sergeants shooting at people in the
ditch and his worst fears were confirmed. With his side gunner, Larry Colburn,
and his crew chief, Glenn Andreotta, Thompson landed the helicopter, telling
Colburn to “open up “ on the GI’s—“open up on ’em, blow ’em away”—if they opened
fire at him as he intervened.
After
some thirty years of silence, the Army belatedly decorated Hugh Thompson with
the prestigious Soldier’s Medal for his valor on that day in My Lai. Shortly
after, he visited Annapolis for a public address, and we spent some time
talking together. What were those moments of sighting the massacre at My Lai
like, I asked. What did he feel? In carefully chosen words, he remembered
thinking that what he witnessed was much like Nazi behavior during the
Holocaust. At the time, he thought American soldiers didn’t behave that way.
They didn’t commit genocide.Hehad shared similar thoughts with the midshipmen that
day, and the traces of anger and disbelief were still visible in his face and
audible in his voice as he recalled approaching the GIs wielding weapons
against innocents. He himself didn’t use the words “moral outrage,” but it was
clear that his judgments about the horrors he saw that day were the judgments
that constitute moral anger. Thirty years later, upon returning to the village
of My Lai for a memorial, he was met by one of the village women who survived
the slayings. He remembered her then as a young mother. She was now a frail,
aging woman.
She
yanked at Thompson’s sleeve and implored, “Why did the American GI’s kill my
family? Why? Why were they different from you?” He broke down in tears and
said, “I don’t know. I don’t know. That is not how I was taught to behave.”25
If we
follow Seneca, do we support an education that would have forced Thompson to
look on with dispassionate disinterest, a kind of Stoic apathy, that could
incite neither rage nor grief? Would we root out the core of Thompson’s virtue
and humanity? Seneca himself is inconsistent on the point. Anger is the clear
enemy in his essay, yet he closes his piece with the following exhortation,
“While we still draw breath, while we still remain among human beings, let us
cultivate our humanity.”26 A
Stoicism committed to the cultivation of humanity and human fellowship cannot,
in fact, eliminate all human anger. As frenzied and blinding as anger’s
outbursts are, as dehumanizing as rage can be, anger expressed in the right way
at the right time is the sure sign of humanity. Aristotle, not the Stoics, got
this point right: anger can be morally fine and praiseworthy. If the Stoics
improve upon Aristotle it is in reminding us that emotions are, more often than
we think, a matter of our responsibility. The Stoics urge that the emotions are
volitional states. We are not just affected when we
suffer emotions, but as the Stoics put it, we yield or give
assent to certain judgments implicit in those emotions.27 Even if
we reluctantly embrace a notion of emotions as voluntary, it is undeniable that
over time we have considerable dominion over how we respond emotionally. We
take charge of how we cultivate our humanity, including, I would add, our
anger.
The
Stoics offer important lessons for the military, and, I would urge, for
civilians as well. They give guidance in shaping a character education that
takes seriously the values of discipline and self-mastery, while recognizing
our dependence upon others not only in small communities, but also globally. We
have seen that Stoic lessons of self-sufficiency and self-mastery are crucial
antidotes to the indulgences of consumerism and appetite that plague the
contemporary scene. The point is not to idealize the life of deprivation or
slavery (as a Stoic like Epictetus may seem sometimes to do), but rather to
cultivate the inner resources and virtues that allow for a measure of control
in the face of strong temptations and hard losses. The Stoic wisdom is that we
have dominion in more areas of our lives than we acknowledge. Our physical
strength can be built, our emotions affect us, but we also regulate them and learn
habits of mind and expression that convey our cares.
The
Stoics make the latter point by suggesting that proper emotions are forms of
judgment that we openly accept and willfully allow. In the case of an emotion
like anger, they say we can control the judgments we consent to and endorse. We
have seen how this stance has both attractions and dangers. We know without
being card-carrying Stoics that reflection allows us to revise overly hasty
views about what may annoy, insult, or offend, and that these revised judgments
help us to change how we feel, in some cases releasing us from the grip of
unreasonable anger. The Stoics, however, insist that all anger is poisoned and that
the truly virtuous person is rid entirely of its venom, but we have argued
against this extreme view. Anger can also show its face as moral outrage,
indignation, and a sense of injustice. There are human moments when anger is
precisely the right response, however much we may lose ourselves in the
reaction. Similarly it is so for grief, compassion, and love. Perhaps the Stoic
lesson is that there are ways of recovering our
mastery even after we have let go, forms of resilience and selfgovernance that
allow for stability in the face of the strongest winds.
The
Stoics also insist upon our cosmopolitan status as citizens of the universe,
not isolated individuals or isolated nations. Military and civic education must
emphasize not only loyalty to country, but also loyalty to values beyond
national borders. My midshipmen needed reminders of their broader citizenship
in the urgent circumstance of chain of command: from whom should they take
orders? For many, the question of whom to respect, obey, and assist are more
diffuse, but the young civilian, no less than the junior military officer,
needs to know that moral obligations and wider circles of allegiance extend
beyond national borders. It is not just our economy that is global, but in a pointed
way, our moral community as well.
I have
turned to the military as a case study for exploring Stoicism and have done so
upon the military’s own lead. Many Navy officers I have worked with have
implicitly and explicitly embraced Stoicism for guidance. I argue that we have
much to reap from the rich Stoic texts. But I also urge a critical attitude in
the face of more orthodox Stoic tenets. The task as moral educators is to shape
a Stoicism with a human face. As Coriolanus, Shakespeare’s legendary Stoic
warrior realized, “it is no little thing to make mine eyes to sweat compassion.”
1. From
James B. Stockdale, Courage Under Fire: Testing
Epictetus’s Doctrines in a Lab of Human Behavior (Stanford: Hoover
Institution Press, 1994).
2. Enchiridion,
Hackett, trans. (Indianapolis: N. White, 1983): 11.
3. For a
good discussion of this, see Jonathan Shay, Achilles in Vietnam (New
York: Simon & Schuster, 1994).
4.
Seneca, “On Anger,” II.31, in Seneca: Moral and Political
Essays, John M. Cooper and J. F. Procop, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1995).
5. As
noted in Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent
Philosophers, R. D. Hicks, trans. (Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1972): 6.63. See also Epictetus, Discourses,W. A.
Oldfather, trans. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1925): 2.10.3,
I.9.2.
6. Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, A. S. L. Farquharson, trans. (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1989): 8.34.
7. See A.
A. Long and D. N. Sedley, The Hellenistic
Philosophers, Vol. 1 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1987): 349.
8. Adam
Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (Indianapolis: Liberty
Classics, 1976 [1759]): 47–48.
9. M. T.
Griffin and E. M. Atkins, eds. On Duties (Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1991): I.96ff. For a very helpful commentary, see
Christopher Gill, “Personhood and Personality: The Four-Personae Theory in
Cicero, De Officiis I” in Oxford
Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Vol. VI (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1988).
10. See
his discussion in Nicomachean Ethics, VII.3, Davis
Ross, trans. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998): VII.3.
11.
Plato’s Republic, G. Grube, trans. (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1974): Book III.
12. J. E.
King, trans., Tusculan Disputations (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1927): IV.13.30.
13. J. M.
Cooper and J. F. Procop, eds., “On Anger” in Seneca: Moral and Political
Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995): I.3.
14. For a
lively discussion, see Sarah Buss, “Appearing Respectful: The Moral
Significance of Etiquette,” in Philosophy and Public
Affairs (1999).
15. J. M.
Cooper and J. F. Procop, eds. “On Favours” in Seneca: Moral and Political
Essays (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1995): II.22.
16. M. T.
Griffin and E. M. Atkins, eds. “On Duties” using Cicero: On Duties (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1991): I.128.
17. See
for example, Seneca, “On Favours,” II.1–2, II.13; “On Duties,” I.93–124.
18. Anthropology
from a Pragmatic Point of View, MaryJ. Gregor, trans.
(The Hague: Nijoff, 1974): 282.
19. See Tusculan
Disputations IV.19.21.
20. See
“On Anger,” III.16.
21.
Ibid., 1.2.
22. See,
for example, the account of emotions in Rhetoric II.
23.
Cicero, Tusculan Disputations, J. E. King, trans.
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1945).
24. For
my account, I have drawn on the report by Michael Hilton and Kevin Sim in their
Four Hours in My Lai (New York: Penguin, 1992).
25. I am
remembering the gist of the conversation as it appeared on CBS’s 60
Minutes.
26. “On
Anger,” III.43. For an insightful discussion of “On Anger,” see Martha
Nussbaum, The Therapy of Desire (Princeton University
Press, 1994): Chapters 10 and 11.
27. For a
nuanced description of the voluntary and involuntary aspects of emotional
experience, see Seneca’s “On Anger,” II.1–4.
==============================
Amitai
Etzioni
America’s
moral and social fabric is weakening. Too often we demand rights without assuming
responsibilities, pursue entitlements while shying away from obligations. More
broadly, as the increase in antisocial behavior over the last decades
indicates, we have lost our commitment to values we all share and few new ones
have arisen to replace those that were lost.
Weshould
not treat violence, drug abuse, illegitimacy, promiscuity, abusive attitudes
toward people of different backgrounds, alcoholism, poor academic performance,
and other social maladies as isolated phenomena. They reflect several social
factors, but key among them is weakness of character—the inability to resist
temptation and adhere to prosocial values. Communitarians maintain that values
do not fly on their own wings. To shore up our moral foundations we must pay attention
to the social institutions that undergird our values. These include the family,
schools, the community (including voluntary associations and places of
worship), and society (as a community of communities).
The focus
here is on one institution, the school. Given that roughly 88 percent of
students still attend public schools, they are what this examination deals
with. It is assumed that even if families—whose societal task is to introduce
children to moral values and lay the foundation of their characters—work
perfectly, schools still need to round off the task. Given the burden and
challenges parents face, they are rarely able to perform their job fully and
hence even more responsibility falls on schools. It follows that schools should
make the development of good character one of their primary responsibilities.
Those who
consider such a mission at the obvious center of education should note that for
quite a few years pressure has been growing to dedicate ever more resources,
energy, and time to teaching everyounger children academics. Newly introduced
tests, on academic subjects, and drives to teach preschool children to read,
all add to the neglect of attention to character education in public schools.
Here are
the high points:
1. Values
education is a crucial part of public education that should be fostered in
schools. There cannot be a value-free or value-neutral education. Schools must
supplement the moral education provided at home, especially when homes are not intact.
2.
Character-building is at the root of upholding values. Without character
education, merely knowing what is right is no assurance that we will do
it and incorporate these values into our lives. Critical to developing
character are the two capabilities of self-discipline and empathy.
Self-discipline is required because without it individuals cannot control their
impulses and will grow up to be uncivil, unethical, and ineffectual. External controls
are needed up to a point but if extended beyond that point, they undermine the
cultivation of self-discipline. Empathy, the capacity to walk in another
person’s shoes, is also essential. It is at the foundation of many values, and
without it those who are self-disciplined might commit themselves to nefarious
purposes.
3.
Character education should imbue students with the full range of school
experiences—the human curriculum as well as the academic curriculum. It should
not be limited to classes on civics, nor is it only a matter of curriculum
content. The way sports are conducted, grades are allotted, teachers behave,
and corridors and parking lots are monitored all import moral messages and
significantly affect character development.
The
preceding observations inform the following specific comments. Extracurricular
activities, especially sports, should not be considered extra, but a vital part
of education. We must strive to develop stronger ties between these activities
and character development. Sport is important not merely for a healthy body and
as a substitute for street activities, but also a way to learn to play by the
rules, bond, develop camaraderie, and much more.
The ways
schools deal with infractions is of special significance for character
education. Schools that ignore petty violence, gross disorder in the corridors,
cafeteria and parking areas, disrespect for the teacher and the facilities, are
undermining character education.The same holds for schools that hand out
rewards (especially grades) too easily, provide automatic promotion and
graduation, and allot rewards on the basis of nonachievement-based
considerations. Peer mentoring of students and patrols of shared spaces, guided
by professionals, is a promising way to enhance character education.
Schools
should teach those values shared by the community, such as veracity and
treating others with dignity. The teaching of values particularly dear to the
heart of subgroups should be reserved for religious and other private schools.
The suggestion that there are only few such values, or that shared commitment
to them holds only as long as they remain highly abstract, is not in line with
the facts.
A public
school should teach about the social role and historical significance of
religion but not advocate a particular religion.Oneought to support efforts
such as those of the Williamsburg Charter to find common ground on religious
issues that divide us and to find space in schools to discuss these issues.
“Value-free”
sex education is unacceptable. Teaching family values without information about
ways to prevent transmission of disease and unwanted pregnancies is dangerous.
We need education for interpersonal relations, family life, and intimacy that
provides a normative context for sex education and shares age-appropriate
specific information on the subject. Students should learn about the value of
delaying sexual involvement and the merits of abstinence while receiving
contraception information to protect them and others if they do become sexually
active. The second message need not cancel out the first one.
Schools
are often expected to correct society’s ills but the opposite must be considered.
Schools need all the external help that can be marshaled to discharge their
duties. Parents and other community members and institutions should see
themselves as partners rather than as outsiders. Parents should be deeply
involved in all aspects of formulating and implementing school policies,
curricula, discipline, community service and, above all, values issues. While
teachers’ and other educators’ professional knowledge should be heeded, on
matters of character the voice of parents and communities should take
precedence, within constitutional limits as long as the policies favored do not
pose a danger to life and limb. (For example, a school may well favor turning
the school into a gun-free zone and oppose a community that favors allowing
students to carry concealed weapons.)
One
should support community schools that also serve as community centers. Schools
should gradually shift to remain open more months a year, longer hours, and
even during weekends. This cannot be done overnight, but the farmers’ calendar
is no longer useful. Community service, when properly conducted, can be an
effective means of developing civic commitments and skills by doing rather than
by merely studying. Although community service should be the practicum for
civics, imposing it on students defeats the purpose of developing the taste for
volunteerism.
Greater
integration must be achieved between work and schooling. Educators need to
search for ways to connect schooling with activities that make sense to young
people. Many businesses that employ high school students part-time ought to
recognize that they are educators as well. These early work experiences will
either reinforce responsible habits and attitudes or serve as lessons in poor
civics and deficient work ethics. Corporations and small businesses should work
with schools to better structure employment opportunities for adolescents to
build character and prepare them for their futures.
Schools
should be viewed as nascent communities. Students and teachers should have the
same basic goals and should be discouraged from approaching one another in an
adversarial or legalistic fashion. Although the basic rights of students must
be fully respected, maintaining civility in schools should not require full
court hearings and the cross-examination of witnesses when disciplining
students. Simplified hearings, limited appeals, mediating, and similar measures
are more appropriate for a school setting. We prefer that disruptive students
receive more education rather than banishment. However, when these measures
fail, schools should not be unduly hampered in removing those who destroy the
learning environment.
Enhanced
diversity in the curricula and in the composition of the school enriches us,
but also exposes us to the dangers of tribalism. Diversity should be advanced,
but within the context of unity. We are richer if we learn about other cultures
and traditions and develop more respect for others. But we must share certain
basics, and above all, the superior value of the democratic form of government,
the importance of the Constitution and its Bill of Rights, and the tolerance of
one another. Educators should be mindful of the theme implied in the saying,
“We all came on different ships but now we ride in the same boat.” No class
should teach hate against another group. We all have troubling parts in our
respective histories. We need to learn reconciliation without forgetting the
lessons of the past, lest we repeat them. Teaching new immigrant children in
their native languages for a limited time may ease their transition, but we
should avoid prolonged separation of education along ethnic or racial lines.
Character
development entails acquiring the capacity to control impulses and to mobilize
for acts other than the satisfaction of one’s self. Workers need such
self-control so that they can stick to their tasks rather than saunter into
work late and turn out slapdash products—so that they are able to observe a
work routine that is often not very satisfying by itself. Citizens and
community members need self-control so that they do not demand ever more
services and handouts while being unwilling to pay taxes and make contributions
to the common good. Self-control makes people more tolerant of others from
different ethnic, racial, and political backgrounds. This tolerance is at the
foundation of democratic societies.
Newborns
have almost no capacity for impulse control or mobilization to tasks that
require deferment of gratification; they are preoccupied with their immediate
needs and desires. Education channels some of these drives to energize an
internal regulator that gives selfdirection to the person and is often referred
to as character. Education ties gratification to the development of qualities that
are socially useful and morally appropriate (a process psychologists call
sublimation). By relating satisfaction to being punctual, completing a task,
and taking other people’s feelings into account, by playing by the rules, one
acquires the ability to abide by moral tenets and to live up to social responsibilities.
It is
possible to overeducate and to draw too much of the ego’s energies into the
inner mechanisms of self-control. This is what is meant by being
“uptight”—people who are obsessed with their careers or achievements are unable
to relax or show affection. Such excessive selfcontrol has concerned social
scientists in the past, especially in the sixties, and has led to a call for
less character education in favor of more unbounded ego expression. Excessive
self-control, however, is uncommon in contemporary America; indeed, many
youngsters come to school with a grossly deficient capacity to guide
themselves. The fact that a larger proportion of the young find it difficult to
be punctual, get up in the morning, do homework on their own, and complete
tasks in an orderly and timely fashion are but the most visible indications of
a much deeper deficiency. As a result, schools must engage in character education.
This is where various commissions that have studied educational deficits went
wrong. By and large, they argue for loading students with more hours of
science, foreign language, math, and other skills and bodies of knowledge. But you
cannot fill a vessel that has yet to be cast.
Character formation is an essential prerequisite—both so that pupils can learn,
and so that by the time they graduate they will command the necessary human
qualities to be effective, responsible adults.
Parents
and educators often stress the importance of discipline in character formation
and in the moral education of the new generation of Americans. In several
public-opinion surveys, teachers, school administrators, and parents rank a
lack of discipline as the number-one problem in our schools. They correctly
perceive that in a classroom where students are restless, impatient,
disorderly, and disrespectful, where rules and routines cannot be developed and
maintained, learning is not possible.
So far,
so good. Unfortunately, discipline, as many people understand it, takes on an
authoritarian meaning. A well-disciplined environment is often considered one
in which teachers and principals lay down the law and will brook no
talking-back from students, who show respect by rising when the teacher enters
the room and speak only when spoken to. In quite a few states physical
punishment is still considered an effective way to maintain discipline. I
maintain that if discipline is achieved by authoritarian means, youngsters will
behave as long as they are closely supervised and fear punishment. But as soon
as the authorities turn their backs, they tend to misbehave and their
resentment at being coerced expresses itself in some form of antisocial
behavior. This is because the discipline is linked to punishment rather than to
a general sense of right and wrong.
What the
pupil—and the future adult—requires is self-discipline, the inner ability to
mobilize and commit to a task he or she believes in and to feel positive—that
is, rewarded—for having done so. This quality is developed when the voice of
authority is internalized and becomes part of the person’s inner self, his ego.
Internalization occurs in structured environments, but not under authoritarian
conditions. What is not needed is close, continuous external supervision (and
certainly not the kind of punitive environment that comes to mind when we think
about military academies). Rather, what is required is a school structure made
up of authority figures, rules, and organization of tasks that motivate students
by providing clear guidelines. These must be both firmly upheld and be
reasonable and justified, so that students can understand the need to abide by
them.
Educational
requirements must, in turn, be clearly stated, and the link between
requirements and goals fully explained. Curricula should be neither arbitrary
nor subject to the whim of an individual teacher. To foster self-discipline,
assignments must be “do-able,” appropriately checked, and properly rewarded.
When they are excessive and mechanical (such as the time one of my high-school
sons was required to memorize the names of all the Indian tribes that resided
in America), or when rewards are allocated according to irrelevant criteria
(such as teacher favoritism, minority status, or undue parental influence),
requirements become dictates and not sources of involvement and ways to
internalize commitments, to build self-discipline.
Although
character formation lays the psychic foundation both for the ability to
mobilize to a task and to behave morally (by being able to control impulses and
defer gratification), it is contentless: it does not educate one to a specific
set of virtues or values. It provides the rectitude needed to tell the truth
even if the consequences are unpleasant, but it does not teach the value of
being truthful. It enables a person to refrain from imposing his sexual impulse
on an unwilling partner, but it does not teach him that it is morally
unacceptable to rape. Developing character without attention to value education
is like trying to develop the muscles of an athlete without having a particular
sport in mind. This statement inevitably raises the question: Whose values? The
challenge “Whose values will you teach?” is readily answered by starting with
the many values that we all share (not only in one community or by Americans,
but much more widely). Nobody considers it moral to abuse children, rape,
steal, commit murder, be disrespectful of others, discriminate, and so on.
Some
values, a small subset of the total in well-functioning communities, are
contested. These exceptions can be dealt with either by letting the students
learn about both sides of the issue or by openly omitting them. Moreover, these
issues are helpful in showing the pain of moral conflicts and the merit of
genuine consensus-building, a consensus we do have on most values. Sure, say
the opponents, but people agree only on vague generalities that almost amount
to banalities. They argue: When you come down to specifics, disagreements will
dominate, and then whose specifics will you teach?
In
response I note that first, we would be way ahead if we could get everyone to
truly subscribe to all these values and only argue with one another over the
specific applications. Second, when it comes to specifics, there is more
consensus than at first seems to be the case. Professor William Damon points to
the following conducts that deserve our attention:
A
counselor is calling a student’s home about apparently excused absences, only
to find that the parent’s letters have been forged. A young boy is in the
principal’s office for threatening his teacher with a knife. Three students are
separated from their class after hurling racial epithets at a fourth. A girl is
complaining that her locker has been broken into and all her belongings stolen.
A small group of boys are huddling in a corner, shielding an exchange of money
for drug packets. In the playground, two girls grab a third and punch her in the
stomach for flirting with the wrong boy. (Personal communication.)
Using
these and other such behaviors as education opportunities is sure to keep
teachers busy for years to come. This suggests that we have to attend to other
sources of these behaviors—for instance, by rebuilding community within the
adult world, which these children often emulate. One need not worry that
educators will brainwash students who are captive audiences in their classrooms
and make them accept their moral viewpoints. Students are exposed to a large variety
of voices, from television, magazines, porn shops, peers, and many others.
There are natural checks and balances built into the social environment. If
somewhere one teacher advanced a moral concept that was outside the community
consensus, say, that we must all become vegetarians, pacifists, or Zen
Buddhists, the students would have plenty of other sources to draw on to
counter such teaching. Indeed, the opposite is true: if typical educators,
whose values tend to be well within the community range, refrain from adding
their moral voices to the cacophony of voices to which the students are
exposed, the students would miss one perspective and remain exposed only to all
the other voices, less committed to values the community holds dear.
How does
one teach moral values, as opposed to merely building up the capacity for moral
reasoning and disputations? How does one build up moral commitments? One way
far surpasses all others: experiences are more effective teachers than lectures
and textbooks, although their narrative is also valuable. This is particularly
evident in extracurricular activities, especially sports. True, these can be
abused, such as when coaches focus on winning as the only object, and neglect
to instill learning to play by the rules, teamwork, and camaraderie. Graduates
of such activities tend to be people who are aggressive, maladjusted members of
the community. However, if coaches and the messages they impart are well
integrated into the values education of a school, and if parents see the
importance of using sports to educate rather than to win, sports can be a most
effective way to enhance values education.
Why do
extracurricular activities command extraordinary power? Because they generate
experiences that are effective educational tools. Thus, if one team plays as a
bunch of individuals and loses because its adversary played as a
well-functioning team, the losing players learn—in a way that no pep talk or
slide show could teach them—the merit of playing as a team.
The same
holds for other activities that take place at school. They provide experiences
that have deep educational effects, either positive or negative. The first step
toward enhancing the moral educational role of schools is to increase the
awareness and analysis of the school as a set of experiences. Schools should be
seen not as a collection of teachers, pupils, classrooms, and curricula.
Instead, we need to include the parking lots: Are they places in which wild
driving takes place and school authorities are not in sight, or places where
one learns respect for others’ safety, regulated either by faculty or fellow
students? Are the cafeterias places where students belt each other with food
and the noise is overwhelming, or civilized places where students have
meaningful conversations over lunch? Are the corridors areas where muscles and
stature are required if one is to avoid being pushed aside by bullies, or are
they safe conduits patrolled by faculty or students? Does vandalism go
unpunished, are drugs sold openly, and are pupils rewarded or punished according
to criteria other than achievement (perhaps because they avoid confrontation,
obey without question, or come from affluent or otherwise socially preferred
backgrounds)? Is vandalism held in check (and when it does occur, the damage
corrected by the offending students), drug sales swiftly and severely dealt
with, and students treated under rational general criteria?
A
powerful example of how one may generate experiences in a classroom is found in
Iowa. It is a well-known case in point, but one that deserves to be recalled.
In 1968, Jane Elliott, a third-grade teacher, concluded that instead of talking
about the plight of black Americans shortly after the assassination of Martin
Luther King, Jr., she would teach her third-graders about discrimination by
affecting their experiences. Elliott divided her class into two groups by eye
color—the blueand brown-eyed. “Today,” she said one Friday, “the blue-eyed
people will be on the bottom and the brown-eyed people on the top.” Elliott continued:
“What I mean is that brown-eyed people are better than blue-eyed people. They
are cleaner than blue-eyed people. They are more civilized than blue-eyed
people. And they are smarter than blueeyed people.”
The experiment’s
effects were swift and severe. “Long before noon, I was sick,” Elliott recalls.
“I wished I had never started it . . . . By the lunch hour, there was no need
to think before identifying a child as blue- or brown-eyed. I could tell simply
by looking at them. The browneyed children were happy, alert, having the times
of their lives. The blue-eyed children were miserable.” The children had
learned through experience what discrimination is like and were deeply affected
by the exercise. Brown-eyed Debbie Anderson said: “I felt mad [on
blue-eyepreferred Monday] . . . I felt dirty. And I did not feel as smart as I
did on Friday.” Student Theodore Perzynski wrote: “I do not like
discrimination. It makes me sad. I would not like to be angry all my life.”
A mother
of one of Elliott’s students said:
I want
you to know that you’ve made a tremendous difference in our lives since your
Discrimination Day exercise. My mother-in-law stays with us a lot, and she
frequently uses the word “nigger.” The very first time she did it after your
lesson, my daughter went up to her and said, “Grandma, we don’t use that word
in our house, and if you’re going to say it, I’m going to leave until you go
home.” We were delighted. I’ve been wanting to say that to her for a long, long
time. And it worked, too. She’s stopped saying it.
Such an
experience leaves a strong and lasting impression. In 1984, Jane Elliott’s
class had a reunion. Former student Susan Rolland reported: “I still find
myself sometimes, when I see some blacks together and I see how they act, I
think, well, that’s black . . . . And then later, as I said, I won’t even
finish the thought before I remember back when I was in that position.” Verla
Buls added: “We was [sic] at a softball game a couple of weekends ago, and
there was this black guy I know. We said, ‘Hi,’ and we hugged each other, and
some people really looked, just like, ‘What are you doing with him?’ And you
just get this burning feeling in you. You just want to let it out and put them
through what we went through to find out they’re not any different.” Other
students reported that their career choices were influenced by the
discrimination experience. Several chose to join the Peace Corps or work with
other cultures overseas.
For
teachers to be more than purveyors of information and skills, for them to be
able to educate, to build character, they must bond more closely with students
than they do now in many schools. Such bonding may be encouraged by arranging
for less rotation of classes and pupils. Many American high schools were
reorganized as if a powerful sociological engineer intent on minimizing the
bonds between students and teachers sought to ensure that whatever peer bonds
formed would not be classroom-based. These effects stem from the fact that
students are reshuffled each time the bell rings, every forty-five minutes or
so, while the various subject teachers stay put. Students, especially in larger
schools, rarely develop bonds as members of a class group, because the class
members they related to in one period are different from the ones they see in
the next. Because of this, peer groups, which often hold sway over members,
especially in moral matters, are not classroom-based and are formed for other
reasons often irrelevant to education. Peer groups are likely to be formed
around other occasions and values, whether it is racing cars or rock music.
This makes it rather difficult for teachers to draw upon these peer bonds and
challenge them to support moral education. Peer groups don’t necessarily have
to oppose community and educational values, but sociological studies show that
they often do, and they rarely are mobilized by educators on the side of moral education
in the typical high-rotation schools.
Another
result is that teachers cannot form bonds with their students, because they
hardly have an opportunity to know them. Teachers are typically responsible for
a subject, and not for a class or a given group of pupils, for example, all
those in the eleventh grade, section five. Thus, the highly specialized school
organization is, in effect, a systematic hindrance to bonding with educators,
which is an essential prerequisite for moral education.
High
schools should be reorganized to facilitate experience-based moral education.
Teachers should be in charge of a particular class, teaching the same group of
youngsters, say, three subjects (especially those rich in value content such as
history and literature), or two subjects and civics. The same teacher would
also be the class’s homeroom teacher, explicitly in charge of disciplinary
matters. Discipline should be sought not as if the teacher were a punitive
police officer, but a faculty member whose task it is to use instances of
improper conduct to enhance moral education. Schools might also institute a
policy whereby such teachers would follow the same students from ninth through
twelfth grades.
Such
changes would, in turn, necessitate changes in the ways the teachers themselves
are trained, to make them less specialized. Many teachers, especially those who
teach humanities or liberal arts, are already broadly grouped. In any event,
without more bonding and contacts that are more encompassing, extensive, and
value-laden, moral education is unlikely to succeed.
This
piece draws, to a limited extent, on Amitai Etzioni, The
Spirit of Community (New York: Crown
Publishers, Inc., 1993).
==============================
F. Clark
Power
Since
1975, I have worked with Lawrence Kohlberg and his colleagues to develop the
Just Community approach to moral education. This approach focuses on building
moral community through involving students in democratic decision-making.
Although the Just Community approach embodies the highest ideals of our nation,
our efforts to disseminate it have met with entrenched resistance. In spite of
the approach’s demonstrated effectiveness in promoting moral development, building
cohesive community, fostering democratic skills, and reducing disciplinary
problems, principals and teachers typically regard it as unrealistic.
Although
schools espouse democracy and community in their mottoes and mission
statements, they are not democracies; principals and teachers govern
autocratically. Few, if any, formal opportunities are available for students to
participate in deciding what matters most to students—school discipline and
social life. Although most schools have some form of student government, its
function is typically and carefully confined to organizing social events and
fund-raisers. Schools beyond the elementary level are not cohesive communities;
cliques and crowds dominate the social landscape. Although most schools pay lip service
to building community through sports programs and school assemblies, few
establish a genuine sense of solidarity that cuts across sex, race, social
class, and friendship group.
Although
the character education movement has been growing rapidly in the United States,
surprisingly little attention has been paid to the school environment. As I
will argue, schools, particularly junior high and high schools, often undermine
character education by fostering cultures inimical to the values taught in
class. Principals and teachers simply fail to recognize how the culture co-opts
their well-intentioned efforts to teach virtue. When we think of schools, we
think of the curriculum, methods of teaching, techniques of discipline, and
specialized remedial and counseling services. We rarely attend to the culture of
the school, except in moments of crisis. Only after shootings in our schools,
for example, have we acknowledged the problem of bullying, long a staple of
peer culture in American junior high and high schools. Yet in spite of our
awareness of the pain that bullying brings about, we have done little or
nothing to address bullying at the cultural level. Instead, we have seen a
rapid rise in metal detectors, lock-down procedures, zero-tolerance policies,
and dress codes. We have speculated about the mysteries of the adolescent
psyche. School officials have responded to the symptoms of violence but not to
their underlying causes. Our superintendents, principals, teachers, and the
wider public have difficulty seeing bullying and breaches of discipline such as
cheating and vandalism as based in the school’s culture. They perceive such problems
in a gestalt that accentuates individual students but not the groups to which
they belong. Until we change the culture of schools into democratic
communities, these problems are likely to persist and our character education
programs to flounder.
Those not
familiar with Kohlberg’s contributions to moral education may be puzzled by his
investment in an approach that places such a strong emphasis on the organization
and culture of the school. Kohlberg became famous for his six-stage theory of
moral judgment, a theory that grew out of Jean Piaget’s cognitive developmental
research. Kohlberg’s stage theory provides a powerful tool for understanding
how children and adolescents think about and resolve moral problems, and his
theory has obvious educational implications. For example, if children reason differently
from their teachers, then teachers have to tailor their moral instruction to
the children’s level. Moreover, if Kohlberg and Piaget are correct that
children construct their moral reasoning through social interaction, then
methods of moral education should treat children as active, not passive,
learners. The most direct application of Kohlberg’s moral psychology is the
dilemma-discussion approach in which leaders encourage students through
Socratic questioning to resolve moral dilemmas. Research shows that when used
appropriately over an extended period, the dilemma-discussion approach is an
effective and reliable way of promoting moral stage development.
When
Kohlberg began his research on the moral stages as a doctoral student in the
late 1950s, the majority of social scientists equated morality with the norms
and values of a particular society. In this view, moral education is reduced to
the socialization or internalization of a society’s standards. Kohlberg, on the
other hand, thought that morality is based on universal principles of justice.
For him, moral education meant the cultivation of moral reasoning. Although
Kohlberg believed that moral education deserved to be undertaken in school, he
questioned the extent to which schools really helped children to develop their
thinking. Kohlberg was fond of describing children as natural moral
philosophers, but he was unsure whether teachers, accustomed to wielding
unquestioned moral authority in the classroom, would be willing to engage in
philosophical dialogue with their students. Kohlberg became involved personally
in moral education only after one of his graduate students, Moshe Blatt,
demonstrated that the dilemmadiscussion approach produced measurable stage
change.
Although
Kohlberg came to education as a psychologist focused on individual moral
development, his early writings about education reveal a nascent and growing
interest in the organization and culture of the school, territory usually
explored by sociologists. Reflecting on the implications of his dissertation
research, Kohlberg suggests in his first article on education that effective
moral education has to address the hierarchical structure of the classroom and
school.1 He finds that the moral reasoning of children from working-class
backgrounds does not develop to the higher moral stages as frequently as that
of their age peers. Noting that such development seemed to require taking the perspective
of those in authority, Kohlberg recommends that schools provide opportunities
for students to participate in decision-making. Several years later in arguably
his best essay on moral education, Kohlberg boldly concludes that in order to
accomplish the goal of moral development schools must provide a special
environment:
The
Platonic view that I have been espousing suggests something still revolutionary
and frightening to me if not to you, that the schools would be radically
different places if they took seriously the teaching of real knowledge of the
good.2
Kohlberg
describes the ideal school as a “little Republic” in which principles of
justice and love are central. Kohlberg’s “little Republic” would be ruled not
by an aristocracy of philosopher-teachers, but by a democracy of teachers and
students engaged in philosophical deliberation about the good of their
community.
Kohlberg’s
theorizing took an even more decisive sociological turn after a visit to an
innovative Israeli Youth Aliyah Kibbutz high school program in 1969. In a
little-known chapter with the revealing title “Cognitive Developmental Theory
and the Practice of Collective Moral Education,” Kohlberg advances a startling
proposal: “Right now, Youth Aliyah Kibbutz youth group practice seems better
than anything we conceive from our theory, and it is not revisions in practice,
but revisions of the way of thinking about it that I am suggesting.”3 Earlier
in his career, Kohlberg had joined Piaget in criticizing the collectivist moral
education advocated by the great French sociologist, Emile Durkheim (1925–1973).4 Kohlberg
saw collectivist moral education as a form of authoritarian indoctrination that
resulted in conformity. His observations of the functioning of a democratic
kibbutz youth group, however, led him to distinguish Durkheim’s collectivism
from that practiced in the totalitarian Soviet Union. After his kibbutz visit,
Kohlberg entertained the possibility that Durkheim’s collectivist theory could
be made compatible with democratic decision-making and that the student peer group
could become a powerful resource for promoting development. Yet how this
strange hybrid of cognitive developmental psychology and collectivist sociology
might serve to guide practice remained a puzzle until Cluster School, the first
experimental Just Community school, opened in 1974.
Kohlberg
completed his sociological turn after working several years in the Cluster
School. As I will illustrate, we learned, often the hard way, that changing the
peer culture required much more than simply leading stimulating moral
discussions. We had to seize every opportunity to convince students to see
themselves as part of a cohesive community and to accept responsibility for
each other and for Cluster’s future. We had to help them to believe that
Cluster’s welfare depended on their willingness to uphold Cluster’s
disciplinary policies and to sacrifice themselves.
Democracy
provides the means of communicating the vision of community and transforming
that vision into a reality. Democracy also serves as the link between
individual and collective development. The most important of the Just
Community’s democratic institutions was the weekly community meeting in which
students and faculty met to discuss community problems and to adopt rules and
policies. Decisions in the community meetings were made through direct
participatory democracy, with each student and faculty member having an equal vote.
Students and faculty prepared for the community meeting by meeting each week in
advisory groups of a dozen or so students and one teacher. These meetings
allowed everyone to discuss the issues that would come before the entire
community; in effect they were dry runs for the larger community meeting.
Infractions of rules and conflicts between students, or between students and
teachers, were taken up in the discipline committee, which in later Just
Community programs has been aptly renamed the fairness committee. This committee,
whose membership rotated every few months, consisted mostly of students. Appeals
of this committee’s decisions went directly to the community meeting.
As we
discovered in Cluster and rediscover each time we start a new Just Community
program, establishing the institutions of participatory democracy is easy;
achieving the ideal of democratic community is not. Living in a representative
democracy, we have little experience deliberating in common about the rules and
policies that affect our daily lives, and often less experience deliberating
about the common good. We live in a time of widespread cynicism about
democratic politics, cynicism that reaches down into our schools. We found in Cluster,
and continue to find, that it takes almost an entire year for faculty and
students to trust that the democratic process can work fairly for everyone.
That kind of trust comes about only through actual experience. Faculty fears of
a tyranny of the student majority and student fears of a sham democracy have,
as we shall see, some basis, but they can be addressed.
The early
days of Cluster were, by all accounts, at times chaotic. Teachers insisted that
the first community meeting be dedicated to planning an innovative afternoon
curriculum. They presented students with an impressive array of elective
courses only to find that the students were less interested in designing the
curriculum than they were testing the extent of their democratic power. One
student interrupted the teacher-dominated discussion with a motion to make
afternoon classes optional. A second quickly followed, and students asked for
an immediate vote. Not surprisingly, the motion carried easily. As the students
got up to leave, Kohlberg, noting that their vote was only a straw vote, stopped
them.
At about
the same time, Kohlberg arranged a field trip for the students to see a movie
at Harvard, which was down the street from the high school. At a community
meeting to prepare for the trip, Kohlberg explained that smoking would not be
permitted in the auditorium where the movie would be shown and he made the trip
conditional upon a democratic decision to prohibit smoking. The students
readily agreed but when the movie began, students casually lit up their
cigarettes. After waiting in vain for the teachers to intervene, Kohlberg
stopped the projector and flicked on the lights. He expressed shock and wonder
that students would so casually violate their democratically made rule.
Kohlberg was less surprised that the students would break the rule than that the
faculty failed to intervene. He quickly realized that this experiment in moral
education would have to begin with the teachers, who were no more experienced
with democratic community than were the students.
Teachers
tend to think of discipline dichotomously, as being either authoritarian or
permissive, and to think of being democratic as being permissive. During the
free-school movement of the 1970s, many teachers idealistically and naively
believed that once the oppressive constraints of authoritarian discipline were
withdrawn, students would naturally be cooperative and responsible. Teachers
were generally reluctant to endorse rules of any type and preferred to
establish guidelines and to deal with compliance issues on an informal,
individual basis. We viewed democracy very differently from most of those
involved with the alternative school movement at that time. First of all, we insisted
that attendance at community meetings be a nonnegotiable requirement for all
students and faculty. Making democracy mandatory seemed contradictory,
particularly to teachers and students in free schools. On the other hand, we
believed that direct participatory democracy was the fundamental principle upon
which the school is established.
We also
thought of democracy as a form of pedagogy. As did John Dewey (1916/1966), we
regarded democratic participation as a means as well as an end of education.5 We
recognized that most high school students are not fully competent to shoulder
the responsibilities of democratic participation. On the other hand, we
believed that they could best acquire democratic competencies as well as a
sense of civic engagement through democratic experience. We therefore adopted
an apprenticeship model of democratic education advanced long ago by Horace Mann,
the founder of the American public school. Mann called attention to the irony
of having authoritarian schools in a democratic nation:
In order
that men may be prepared for self-government, their apprenticeship must begin
in childhood . . . He who has been a serf until the day before he is twenty-one
years of age, cannot be an independent citizen the day after; and it makes no
difference whether he has been a serf in Austria or America. As the fitting
apprenticeship for despotism consists in being trained for despotism, so the
fitting apprenticeship for self-government consists in being trained to
self-government.6
The
apprenticeship model has two essential features. First, it is a learn-by-doing
approach that gives students regular opportunities to practice democratic
decision-making. Second, it is a training approach that provides direction and
guidance. Although democracy involves an egalitarian relationship between
teachers and students, an apprenticeship is by nature hierarchical. An
apprenticeship in democracy may thus appear to be contradictory. Yet the
hierarchy of an apprenticeship is primarily established, not through positional
authority but through expertise and experience. In a democratic apprenticeship,
the teachers’ expertise is exercised primarily through their persuasiveness and
organizational responsibility in establishing and maintaining democratic institutions.
We may
ask, however, whether teachers can be both leaders and equal members of a
democratic school. In his classic The Moral Education of the
Child, Piaget (1932/1965) raises serious problems for such a view.7 He
postulates that there are two moralities of the child: a morality of constraint
of the adult over the child and a morality of cooperation among children. A
morality of constraint follows almost inevitably from the hierarchical
relationship of adult to child. A morality of cooperation develops out of peer
relationships. These moralities operate in diametrically different ways. A
morality of constraint is one of subservient compliance to a superior
authority—reason has no place in this morality because the child bases respect
for authority on the mere fact of the adult’s superior power. A morality of
cooperation, on the other hand, is one of collaboration among equals—reason is
central to this morality because the children must freely establish their own rules
and norms. Piaget denounces the monarchical authority that leads teachers to
foster mindless conformity in their students. Such an approach, he writes,
ignores the facts of child development and fosters rebellion at worst and
passivity at the very least.
We agree
with Piaget that adults can and often do get in the way of the development of
children’s moral judgment. As I noted earlier, Kohlberg’s research on moral
discussions showed that to be effective, teachers had to use a Socratic
questioning approach. Nothing can short-circuit a discussion more quickly than
a teacher who answers his or her own question or requires students to guess at
the right answer. We believe that teachers have to engage students in serious
moral dialogue, which entails careful listening as well as questioning. This
means that teachers must set aside their roles as the authority who possesses
the truth to assume the role of fellow inquirer. In a democratic school, this
means that teachers should act as equal members of the group or, in Piaget’s terms,
as elder collaborators. When necessary, teachers should also act as
facilitators of moral discussion and the democratic process. The apprenticeship
model suggests that the teachers’ role extends beyond that of facilitator to
that of exemplar or leader.
Only
after several years of consultation at Cluster did we manage to articulate the
complex role that teachers should play in the Just Community democracy. The
role entailed maintaining a delicate balance between offering direction and
releasing control. Teachers had to encourage students to feel a sense of
ownership of the school while challenging them to strive for the ideals of community.
At times, teachers had to withhold their own opinions in order to facilitate
student discussion; at other times, the teachers had to speak out on behalf of
the community, or sometimes on behalf of their own interests.
Kohlberg’s
thinking about the teacher’s role was heavily influenced by his observations of
the madrich, the adult leader in a kibbutz school. Kohlberg
reported that through the madrich’s skillful
but subtle direction, the students formed an unusually cohesive and
well-disciplined community. Kohlberg noted, “Underneath the informality of the madrich there is
a considerable amount of iron, and this iron is based on the theory of
collective education.”8 The madrich seldom
gave orders or speeches, but he understood and made use of the power of the
peer group. There is no clear counterpart to the madrich in the
American education system. The madrich assumed
some of the familiar functions of principal, counselor, and homeroom teacher,
yet the madrich’s major contribution was to
work through the democratic process to involve students in building community.
Although
we tried to help the Cluster teachers to adopt a role similar to that of the madrich,we had
little initial success. Junior-high and highschool teachers see themselves
primarily as responsible for teaching their subject, for example, history,
science, or math. Unless they teach a civics education course, they do not see
themselves as responsible for preparing students for democratic citizenship.
Moreover, they are generally uncomfortable about their roles as
disciplinarians. Most teachers think of discipline as control or management, a
necessary but unpleasant way of securing the conditions that allow them to
teach. Interviews that my students and I have conducted reveal that they have
difficulty even imagining discipline as “the morality of the classroom”
(Durkheim, 1925/1973) or discipline as an educational activity.9 Before we
were able to help the Cluster teachers forge their role in the Just Community approach,
we had to persuade them that deliberating about disciplinary problems in a
democratic context was worth the time and effort. We had to help them become
aware of the value of listening to students rather than simply preaching to
them.
I
demonstrate the benefits as well as the challenge of envisioning a new
disciplinary role for teachers with a simple example taken from a conventional
junior high school. The teacher, Ms. Jones, was known as one of the best
teachers in the junior high school. She related well to students and was
interested in learning more about moral education. In the middle of the school
year, she discovered that one of her advanced students, Susan, had given her
assignment to Joey, who had copied it. She swiftly punished Susan and Joey for
cheating by giving them failing grades for the assignment, calling their
parents, and excluding them from the monthly good-behavior pizza party. When I
became aware of this incident, I thought that it might provide a teachable
moment for Ms. Jones to explore the issue of copying assignments with her class
and maybe even for her to involve students in making a rule prohibiting such
collaboration as well as more serious kinds of cheating. I suggested to Ms.
Jones that the students who cheated may not have felt that what they had done
was really wrong, and recommended that she hold a class discussion about such
copying to ascertain what her students thought. If her students did not think
that it was wrong, then she might have to reconsider her punitive response and,
at the very least, lead a moral discussion on cheating.
Ms. Jones
agreed to the discussion although she expressed skepticism about its necessity.
The following day she asked the class, “Who here believes that lending your
class assignment to another student isn’t cheating?” The students snickered but
not a hand went up. Ms. Jones concluded by reminding her students that the
rules she had distributed in writing at the beginning of the school year
clearly forbade such cheating, and she expected no more incidents. After class
dismissal, another student was overheard asking Susan to let her copy her
homework over the lunch period.
This
example illustrates the futility of an authoritarian approach to discipline.
Ms. Jones established and enforced the classroom rules without involving the
students. However, she did not believe that she was simply asserting her
authority as a teacher or that she was demanding obedience to an arbitrary or
irrational rule. The purpose of homework, mastery of the material, is
undermined by copying someone else’s answers. Copying, moreover, is dishonest.
Students surely know or at least can readily recognize the point that this is
true. Would explaining the educational benefits of doing one’s own work or the
importance of honesty have made any difference in Susan’s or anyone else’s
behavior?
In my
view, the problem was not a matter of student ignorance or ill will but a
problem of the peer culture. Students did not think about copying in moral
terms. In fact, the students had developed a norm among themselves in which
copying was understood as helping. In order to change the peer culture, Ms.
Jones would first have had to invite her students to share their views on the
matter. What would students have replied if Ms. Jones had asked them what they
thought about copying?WhenI later asked Susan why she cheated, she objected, “Cheating?
I thought that I was helping, that I was being a Mother Teresa.” If Susan had
participated in a genuine moral discussion with her peers, she would likely
have defended her action as being harmless at worst (Joey usually did his own
work) and altruistic at best (not only was she helping a friend who had fallen
behind but also all the students in the advanced group who had to wait for him
to finish). Ms. Jones would have been in a good position to suggest to Susan
and her peers that a better way of helping Joey may have been to encourage him
to finish the work on his own. Ms. Jones could also have discussed the matters
of honesty and the importance of trust in the classroom. Eventually Ms. Jones
could have asked the class to come up with a rule for assignments to express
the values of working on one’s own, honesty, and trust.
In
sketching out how Ms. Jones could have acted, I wish not to blame her. She is
to be commended for the moral seriousness with which she responded to the
incident in her class. Many teachers might have looked the other way or failed
to realize that moral issues were at stake. Ms. Jones’s response was,
nevertheless, ineffectual—possibly even counterproductive. She could have acted
differently with a far greater probability of success, but unfortunately could
not perceive another way of acting. Teachers are neither prepared for nor
expected to lead moral discussions about classroom discipline, let alone to organize
their classrooms to provide an apprenticeship in democracy. Teachers are not trained
to play the role of the madrich in
mobilizing students to build a better community to attend to the peer culture.
Ms. Jones punished Susan and Joey, assuming that this would deter them and
others in the future. The punishment, however, appeared to deter no one except Susan,
who refused to lend her homework the next time she was asked. When I later
asked her why she did not lend her homework, she stated simply that she did not
want to get in trouble. She confided that she felt angry and betrayed, and that
her friends supported her. It appears that the deterrent approach not only
failed to influence Susan’s moral reasoning but also alienated Susan and her
peers from the teacher, and to some extent from the school itself.
Analyzing
the effectiveness of the conventional classroom management approach to
discipline from the standpoint of moral education will, I believe, lead to the
exploration of alternatives such as the Just Community approach, which address
student culture as well as moral reasoning. We need to be able to bridge the
culture gap, identified long ago by Willard Waller, who depicted teachers and
their students as living two different, almost impenetrable social worlds.10 The
students, he found, tend to bond together in strong primary groups, which
teachers try to control from the outside, as it were, through extrinsic rewards
and punishments. As I have illustrated, the mechanisms of extrinsic control
only further alienate the student culture. In order to break down the barriers
between teachers and students, teachers need to appeal to the student culture
from the inside. This is what the Just Community approach tries to do by asking
teachers to share power as well as responsibility in enabling students to build
a cohesive moral community.
The
teacher’s role in the Just Community encompasses more than that of facilitator
and elder collaborator—teachers must be willing to guide and to lead. As was
evident from the earliest Cluster community meetings, teachers need to impress
upon students the need for careful deliberation before coming to a decision.
Teachers may also be called upon to give direction to discussions by speaking
out on behalf of the ideals of the community. Kohlberg played this role in the
early days of Cluster, and we wanted faculty to assume it as soon as possible;
we conceived this role as that of advocate. In formalizing it, we were all too aware
that teachers could easily abuse it. On the other hand, we recognized that the
Cluster democracy would flounder without Kohlberg and the teachers consistently
appealing to the two pillars of the Just Community approach: democracy and
community. These pillars are not just descriptive aspects of an institutional
reality, they are normative ideals. Cluster had to become a democracy by
developing depth of participation, and a community by developing bonds of
caring, trust, and responsibility.
Building
Community through Collective Norms
I
conclude this chapter by discussing our understanding of community and how we
tried to build it through establishing what we called collective norms. We
defined community as a group in which members value their common life for its
own sake, distinguishing community from an association in which relationships
among the members are valued instrumentally. The kind of community that we
endeavored to develop through the Just Community approach was one characterized
by shared expectations for a high degree of solidarity, care, trust, and participation
in group activities. These expectations did not arise spontaneously but had to
be carefully cultivated over time.
We
discovered early that the opportunity to vote on rules was insufficient to
change student behavior. Students were accustomed to having rules against
disrupting class, fighting, stealing, and skipping class; but these rules were
enforced by the teachers through personal charisma or threat. We wanted to get
the student peer group behind the rule. This meant that students would have to
view the rules as expressing the shared expectations of the community. How
could one lead students to have enough of a sense of ownership of the school so
that they cared about the welfare of the community as a whole? Making rules
democratically after considerable discussion helped enormously. Over time,
students felt a sense of ownership of the school and increasingly accepted
responsibility for resolving disciplinary problems, yet the students typically
tried to address problems extrinsically through the threat of punishment rather
than intrinsically through appealing to each other’s commitment to the
community’s core values.
We first
used the term “collective norm” to describe the shared expectations that we
were trying to engender through community meeting discussions when we compared
transcripts from two community meetings focused on the issue of stealing (see
Power, Higgins, and Kohberg).11 The first
meeting took place during Cluster’s first year and resulted in a rule
prohibiting stealing; the second, the following year, resulted in a decision
that everyone should chip in to reimburse a theft victim in the school.
Webelieved that a sense of community had clearly developed from the first to
the second year. We were hard-pressed, however, to describe the change in the
community’s culture to distinguish it from the stage change simultaneously
occurring in the individual student’s moral reasoning.
When
stealing first occurred in Cluster, the students were nonchalant. “School isn’t
a place for trusting stuff, even at Cluster. Community or not, if you want
something, you’ll take it. It [stealing] goes to show you can’t be too
friendly.” When Kohlberg attempted to arouse a feeling of moral indignation
about the lack of trust and community, a student shot back, “Just because a few
things were stolen, you don’t have to cry about it.” Many students seemed to
think that stealing was wrong simply because it was a violation of one’s
concrete right of ownership (what Kohlberg scored as Stage 2 reasoning). Others
voiced the more advanced insight that stealing was a violation of interpersonal
trust (Stage 3): “I know lots of people who steal . . . and you really feel bad
about that.” Even those students conceded that there was not much that could be
done about stealing besides establishing a punishment that might deter
potential thieves. By the following year, the focus of the discussion had
shifted radically. Many more students spoke up than in the previous year, and
the majority seemed to be invested in Kohlberg’s vision of community.
Phyllis: It is
everyone’s fault that she don’t have no money. It was stolen because people
don’t care about the community. [They think] they are all individuals and don’t
have to be included in the community. Everybody should care that she got her
money stolen [and therefore] we [those students in Phyllis’s advisory group]
decided to give her money back to her.
Bob: That
somebody stole the money is pretty bad, but to me, that I have to pay because
she lost her money is like someone robbing a bank and the bank owner comes to
my door and asks me to pay a couple of bucks because they lost their money.
That’s crazy!
Albert: What’s
your definition of community?
Bob: Mydefinition
of community is that people can help one another right there. But I didn’t say
nothing about giving money out.
Albert: The money
was lost or stolen or whatever and it’s not really to return the money, it is
to help someone in the community altogether. I think it would be the first
really community thing that we have ever done, really. It doesn’t concern the
money, it concerns community action.
Peggy: I think
that if Bob feels so strongly about [giving] his fifteen cents to Monica that
he shouldn’t belong in this community. I am sure that if it was his money he
would feel the other way around. He wouldn’t want nine dollars taken from him,
he would be crying.12
Kohlberg
and I were especially intrigued with Phyllis’s comments because, in addition to
expressing her own point of view, she seemed to be speaking on behalf of the
Cluster community. According to Kohlberg’s stage theory, Phyllis saw the
problem of stealing as more than a concrete loss of property (Stage 2), but as
a lack of interpersonal caring (Stage 3). Albert and Peggy clearly agreed with
Phyllis for similar, Stage-3 reasons. Kohlberg and I found that on the whole,
there were far more instances of Stage-3 reasoning in this second meeting than
in the first, suggesting that the modal stage of the group may have developed
from Stage 2 to Stage 3. Yet this depiction of the change between the two years
failed to capture the way in which Phyllis, Albert, and Peggy appeared to be
speaking as representatives of the Cluster community and not just for
themselves as individuals. Phyllis says, “Everybody should care that she got
her money stolen” and earlier that the theft was “everyone’s fault.” Phyllis is
clearly voicing more than her personal opinion about stealing. She is
expressing a norm that she believes binds her fellow students not only as
individuals but as members of the community. Phyllis, moreover, is not merely
proposing that the community adopt norms of trust and caring as Kohlberg did in
the previous year. Phyllis assumes that the community has accepted these norms
and expresses disappointment that some members have not lived up to them. Her
statements as well as Albert’s and Peggy’s suggest that the culture of Cluster
had changed dramatically. Over the course of a year, Cluster appeared to have
developed from a collection of individuals with very low aspirations for their
common life to a community in which members are expected to care for and trust
one another.
How can
we be certain that Phyllis and others represented the wider group? There were
students like Bob in Cluster, who did not understand or did not agree with the
concept of community that Phyllis, Albert, and Peggy advanced.The best that we
could hope for was that increasing numbers of students would share a vision of
Cluster and ask each other to begin to realize that vision. Each time a class
graduated and a new class joined the school, that vision would have to be
communicated and the group’s norms renegotiated. Looking over that second
meeting, we were encouraged that most of the students who spoke sided with Phyllis,
Albert, and Peggy, and that the vast majority of the community voted in favor
of Phyllis’s motion for restitution. Interviews with students that year
confirmed that, indeed, Phyllis had spoken for the majority of the students. A
consensus was emerging about what membership in the Cluster community entailed.
Through
the process of identifying the development of collective norms, we came to
understand more clearly what the Just Community approach demands and why it is
so counter-cultural. If we really want schools to become communities
characterized by trust, caring, and shared responsibility, teachers and
students must engage in serious moral dialogue about their common life. They
have to use the democratic process as a means of communicating a vision and
establishing shared expectations. In making and enforcing rules, they need to
ask themselves whether their decisions reflect a commitment to foster the welfare
and solidarity of the community or whether their decisions reflect their own
interests or that of a subgroup.
As I
illustrated in the example of Susan’s cheating, teachers do not habitually
deliberate about disciplinary and school life issues with students, nor build
community, by asking students to make sacrifices for worthy ideals. Ironically,
Bob’s depiction of the school as a bank may well be accurate for conventional
schools. We join banks for instrumental, self-serving purposes; banks cannot
ask us to be responsible for each other’s or the bank’s welfare. The more
schools resemble banks, the less effective they are in fostering moral
development. Our experience with the Just Community approach in Cluster and in
subsequent projects suggests that schools can buck the culture; they do not
have to be like banks.
Some have
asked whether the Just Community programs have more than a temporary,
context-specific influence on their students. Why focus on developing
collective norms within a particular school? What happens when students leave
the community? I maintain that the experience of democratically participating
in moral community fosters general confidence in the democratic process and
commitment to the common good. There is now some quantitative evidence to
support me. Grady found that ten years after their graduation, Cluster alumnae and
alumni were more likely than their peers to have an interest in politics and
national affairs; to have voted in local elections; to have a concern for local
government decisions; and to have worked with others in a community to solve
community problems.13
There is
now an unprecedented commitment at the federal, state, and local levels to
promote character education in our nation’s schools. As programs proliferate,
we should be wary of programs that proclaim the virtues in abstract and
superficial ways but do not touch students’ hearts or minds. We should be
sensitive to the fact that the values that we espouse in such programs are
often not the values that are reflected in the institutional and cultural life
of the school. We should be concerned that although we live in a democratic
society, our schools are not democratic. If the Just Community approach seems
radical today, it is because our schools are not the places that they should be
and we have not prepared our teachers and our principals as we should. The Just
Community approach is radical in the sense that it is rooted in the principles
of democracy and community upon which our nation stands. We should, like
Kohlberg, ask our schools to become “little republics,” challenging our
students to commit themselves to a higher good and in so doing fostering the
development of moral responsibility and civic engagement.
1. L.
Kohlberg, “Moral Education in the School,” School Review 74
(1966): 1–30.
2. L.
Kohlberg, “Education for Justice: A Modern Restatement of the Platonic View,”
in N. Sizer and T. Sizer, eds., Moral Education: Five
Lectures (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970): 83.
3. L.
Kohlberg, “Cognitive Developmental Theory and the Practice of Collective Moral
Education,” in M. Wolins and M. Gottesman, eds., Group Care: An Israeli
Approach (New York: Gordon and Breach, 1971): 370.
4. E.
Durkheim, Moral Education: A Study in the Theory and Application of the Sociology
of Education (New York: Free Press, 1925/1973).
5. J.
Dewey, Democracy and Education (New York: Free Press,
1916/1966).
6. H.
Mann, The Republic and the School: The Education of Free Men (New
York: Teachers College, Columbia University, 1845/1957): 58.
7. J.
Piaget, The Moral Judgment of the Child (New York: Free Press,
1965; original work published in 1932).
8. See
Kohlberg (1971): 358.
9. E.
Durkheim, Moral Education: A Study in the Theory and Application of the Sociology
of Education (New York: Free Press, 1925/1973): 1448.
10. W.
Waller, The Sociology of Teaching (New York: John Wiley &
Sons, 1932).
11. F. C.
Power, A. Higgins, and L. Kohlberg, Lawrence Kohlberg’s
Approach to Moral Education (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1989).
12.
Ibid., 113–114.
13. E. A.
Grady, “After Cluster School: A Study of the Impact in Adulthood of a Moral
Education Intervention Project.” Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Harvard
University, 1994.
==============================
Anne
Colby
Two
powerful currents flowing through contemporary American higher
education are pulling the field in different directions. The stronger of the
two is a trend toward specialization and commercialization. This current is
leading to the creation of an education industry that is responsive to market
pressures, concentrating on preparing workers suited to American industry and
giving students skills to compete economically so they can lead more
comfortable, affluent lives. In this model, students are treated as consumers
who invest time and money in higher education in order to receive future
economic benefits. This increasingly powerful corporate model of higher
education imports the values assumptions, language, and administrative policies
of the business world, including marketing and market research, corporate
management strategies, and aggressive public-relations campaigns. This conception
of higher education is part of a longer-term historical change in the way
higher education’s purposes are understood, a shift away from an earlier
conception of the public purposes of higher education and toward a more
individualistic, technical, and morally disinterested understanding
of those purposes.
At the
same time that universities move in this specialized and narrowly market-driven
direction, we see a groundswell of interest in higher education’s capacity to
contribute to stronger communities, a more responsive democratic system, and
more engaged citizens. Critics from outside and within the academy are joining
a chorus of calls to revitalize the public purposes of higher education,
including educating for students’ moral and civic development, as well as
technical and more narrowly intellectual learning. The urgency of these calls
is reinforced by a society-wide concern about the extent to which citizens, especially
young people, are disengaged from public life.
I believe
there is reason for serious concern about higher education’s move toward a
corporate and individualistic approach, and that we need to support the growing
but still somewhat peripheral movement to make higher education a force for
strengthening American democracy. Borrowing ideas and practices from the
business world may increase the efficiency and effectiveness of institutions of
higher education in some ways, and has no doubt made schools more responsive to
the interests of their students. Heavy reliance on a corporate model, however, risks
obscuring important differences between profit-making businesses and nonprofit
educational institutions. Although financial viability is an obvious
prerequisite to the continued existence of a college or university, if used as
the overriding criterion for setting and evaluating priorities and policies, it
will subordinate concern for many important learning outcomes and public
purposes to a narrow understanding of educational goals.
Many
kinds of social institution play important roles in educating citizens.
Religious organizations and other voluntary associations, the media, and
education at the elementary and secondary levels are among the most important
of these. But higher education is critical because universities and colleges
are the institutions most clearly charged with leading the development of new
and deeper understanding through research and scholarship, and preparing new
generations by teaching not only information and skills, but their significance
for personally and collectively creating the future. Higher education has
tremendous opportunities as a positive force in society as it reaches an
ever-larger segment of the population, including virtually all leaders in
government and the private sector. It is a powerful influence in shaping
individuals’ relationships with each other and their communities, and we need
to ensure that its influence is constructive rather than corrosive. There is no
question that higher education has begun to respond to these concerns. In
response to calls for a renewal of civic engagement and social responsibility,
colleges and universities are becoming more directly involved in efforts to
address social problems in their local communities, for example by developing
partnerships with local schools or establishing public forums for discussion of
political and policy issues.
In
addition to this kind of institutional engagement, some colleges and
universities have begun to place greater emphasis on student outcomes that
concern public service, civic participation and leadership, and humane or
ethical values and behavior. This is apparent in the proliferation of
curricular and extracurricular programs designed to foster the development of
students’ moral and civic responsibility, such as ethics across the curriculum,
service-learning, and community service programs such as alternative spring
break.
Educational
leaders have established a number of national networks to support this kind of
work, the most visible of which are networks concerned with service-learning,
such as Campus Compact and the Learn and Serve Higher Education initiative of
the Corporation for National Service. In addition to the development of these
specialized networks, national organizations of higher education such as the
Association of American Colleges and Universities and the American Association of
Higher Education are placing these concerns at the center of their agendas.
Communication about this work is broadening its reach as national conferences
are held on college student values and education for civic participation.
But even
as this movement to reinstate the public purposes of higher education
strengthens, there are powerful points of resistance to it. Whether the
movement can significantly temper the trend toward education as a commodity for
individual advancement is very much in question. Higher education could
continue to drift loose from its moorings as an institution for the public good
and move farther down the path toward market-driven training unconcerned with
the education of the student as person and citizen. A number of arguments are
raised over and over to justify giving up higher education’s moral and civic purposes,
to make these goals seem obsolete in the contemporary world. These arguments
are widespread and threaten to nip in the bud the revival of the public
purposes of higher education, or at least to keep it very much on the margin of
academic life. This essay will argue that these objections are misplaced,
ill-informed, and incorrect.
The first
of these arguments is that higher education has no business addressing issues
of values: it should be value-neutral, impart knowledge and skills, and leave
questions of moral and civic values to the family, the church, and political
institutions. Although this recommendation may seem plausible at first glance,
closer scrutiny makes it clear that educational institutions cannot be
value-neutral. For decades educators have recognized the power of the hidden
curriculum in schools and the moral messages it carries.1 The
hidden curriculum is the (largely unexamined) practices through which the
school and its teachers operate—maintain discipline, assign grades and other
rewards, and manage their relationships with their students and each other.
Although most research on the hidden curriculum has been directed toward elementary
and secondary education, the concept applies equally to higher education. If
college students see faculty rewarded for pursuing their own professional
prestige rather than caring for others or the institution, if they are
subjected to competitive climates in which one student’s success contributes to
another’s failure, if they are confronted with institutional hypocrisy, they
themselves can become cynical and self-interested. On the other hand, when
faculty are scrupulously honest, fair, and caring with their students and
approach their scholarship with integrity, they teach powerful moral lessons of
a very different sort. In addition to these values messages in relations
between faculty and students, messages of instrumental individualism and
materialism are more and more prevalent in the broader institutional and peer cultures
on many campuses. The commercialization of higher education, including
corporate sponsorship of faculty and student research, corporate underwriting
of certain courses, advertising on websites, and exclusive beverage-pouring
rights given to products such as Coke or Pepsi at sports and other events,
though it provides some institutional benefits, also acts to reinforce themes
of materialism and commercialism that are pervasive in the general culture. Few
would deny the influence of commercial interests on the informal learning
contexts in which college students are immersed through television, film,
music, and other media. When higher education reinforces these cultural trends,
it may appear to be value-neutral, but clearly it is not.
Academic
disciplines also embody values assumptions that contribute to shaping students’
frames of reference, though these assumptions are often unexamined and thus
invisible. The preponderance of research in economics and much of that in
political science, for example, build on a model that assumes rational choice,
which is seldom subjected to critical analysis in the teaching of these
disciplines. This model of human behavior assumes that individuals always seek
to maximize their perceived interests and that social phenomena represent the
aggregate of individuals employing this self-interested strategy. A similar perspective
is fostered by research and theory in other fields such as sociobiology and
some approaches within psychology, which also assume a self-interested or
mechanistic view of human nature. An unquestioned reliance on these models of
human behavior can result in a normalization of self-interestedness,
contributing to the common belief that individuals are always fundamentally
motivated by self-interest, that altruism or genuine concern for others’
welfare are illusory, and that failing to act strategically to achieve one’s
own self-interested goals would be foolish.2
In many
disciplines, including such wide-ranging fields as literature, genetics,
engineering, and business, moral issues are integral to the material, and
teaching that does not address them is itself a lesson in a particular way to
orient to complex, multidimensional material. James Rest, Muriel Bebeau, Janet
Walker, and others have written about the central role of interpretation and
sensitivity to moral issues in moral understanding and behavior.3 In a
recent paper Janet Walker explores the implications of the fact that most life
situations are inherently ambiguous, their moral significance underdetermined
by available facts.
In order
to find meaning and clarity amid this ambiguity, people develop habits of moral
interpretation and intuition through which they perceive the world. In effect,
people with different habits of moral interpretation live in worlds that can be
very different, although they have much in common, and these worlds present
different opportunities and imperatives for moral action.
Over and
over in their undergraduate careers, students encounter course material that
raises salient moral issues, but in most classrooms these issues are
consistently set aside as irrelevant to understanding the material. This
constitutes systematic, though unintentional, training in habits of moral
interpretation that teach students to turn a blind eye toward the moral issues
implicit in many situations. In these and many other ways, educational
institutions convey values and moral messages to their students. This is
unavoidable. Given this reality, it seems preferable for these institutions to
examine their values and make more conscious, deliberate choices about what
they convey to students. This brings us back into controversy, since in making
these choices, educational institutions are forced to confront the pluralistic
nature of our society and thus of our faculty and student bodies.
One
effort to remain apparently value-neutral while educating responsible citizens
is through the cultivation of “value-free” or “content-free” skills of
intellectual discipline, critical thinking, and analytical reasoning. These
goals are, after all, at the heart of higher education’s academic identity.
Although fostering civic participation or engagement is also quite likely to be
regarded as safely value-neutral and thus theoretically relatively benign, in
practice it raises questions about the political ideologies that lie behind it,
and therefore begins to encounter resistance.
The most
heated objections arise relative to approaches that include concern for
morality, character, and values along with attention to civic engagement and
responsibility. Questions of whose values, assumptions of indoctrination, and
complaints that “this is not the proper role of higher education,” begin in
earnest as soon as the word “morality” is used.
Why not,
then, focus on the development of skills needed for effective citizenship,
including such undeniably valuable capacities as critical thinking, and leave
the development of values and morality to the private sphere? My colleagues and
I have argued elsewhere that this is neither desirable nor even possible. To
assume that cultivation of core academic capacities such as analytical thinking
and disinterested scientific and scholarly expertise is sufficient to produce
responsible citizens who will devote themselves to the common good of society
begs the question of motivation to do so and flies in the face of extensive evidence
of contemporary civic and political disengagement, particularly among young
people. There is plenty of evidence that recipients of this kind of education
are choosing more and more to apply their analytic skills and professional
expertise to their own personal advancement, and the educational approach
described here does not presume to address that trend.
Can we
focus on education for civic responsibility and thereby avoid addressing the
most controversial area of moral values?
This move will not work either, because education for democratic participation
necessarily engages moral issues. Our democratic principles, including tolerance
and respect for others, procedural impartiality, and concern for both the
rights of the individual and the welfare of the group, are all grounded in
moral principles.
Likewise,
the problems that the civically engaged citizen must confront always include
strong moral themes—for example, fair access to resources such as housing, the
moral obligation to consider future generations in making environmental policy,
and the conflicting claims of multiple stakeholders in community
decision-making. None of these issues can be resolved adequately without a
consideration of moral questions. A person can become civically and politically
active without good judgment and a strong moral compass, but it is hardly wise
to promote that kind of involvement. Because civic responsibility is
inescapably threaded with moral values, higher education must aspire to foster
both moral and civic maturity and must confront educationally the many links
between them.
This
brings us to the second common objection to undergraduate moral and civic
education: we live in a pluralistic society, so there is no legitimate way to
determine which (or whose) values ought to be conveyed. This objection takes
two forms. The first derives from the diversity that characterizes contemporary
American society, which comprises people of many cultural backgrounds and
traditions, religions, and political perspectives. The second reflects the
recognition that within any given cultural tradition, there are reasonable
variations and disagreements about many moral, civic, political, and religious issues.
In
addressing these concerns, it is important to distinguish between pluralism and
moral relativism. A pluralistic view of morality assumes that two or more
incommensurable moral frameworks can be justified. This does not mean that any possible
moral framework is justifiable, only that there are multiple valid moral
frameworks that cannot be reduced to a single system. In contrast, moral
relativism holds that there is no basis at all for distinguishing among moral
positions, that none can be considered any more or less valid than any other.
Few critics of moral and civic education are relativistic in this sense. If
they were, they would not be able to argue with any credibility that
universities ought not indoctrinate their students with an arbitrary set of
values, since this argument is itself a moral claim that, presumably, they feel
they can justify on moral grounds.
For many
years, anthropologists have documented the plural norms that exist in different
cultures throughout the world (diversity in what people do or believe they
ought to do). Some have argued that this diversity of norms is superficial and,
once its meaning is understood, it reduces to underlying moral principles
common to all cultures. Others have tried to show that cultural diversity
reflects fundamental differences in moral perspectives, so that the values most
important in one culture are much less central or salient in another. Richard
Shweder has done extensive field work to document the fact that moral concepts such
as autonomy, individual rights, and justice, which are central to American and
European conceptions of morality, are, in other cultures such as India,
overshadowed by other more elaborated and salient moral concepts such as duty,
sacrifice, and loyalty.4 It is
important to note, however, that even in anthropological research documenting
cultural differences in moral values, there are boundaries to the range of what
is seen to count as an ultimate moral good, and that even very different moral
perspectives include (though they do not stress) the values of the other
perspectives. Differences in moral frames of reference are best seen as
differences in how a common set of base values are ordered when they conflict,
and which of those values are more salient in practice. Even anthropologists
who believe there is fundamental moral heterogeneity across cultures do not
generally believe in extreme and unqualified cultural relativism. Even very
different (and fundamentally incommensurate) moral perspectives build on a base
set of moral goods or virtues that human beings have in common. Presumably,
these commonalities will be even stronger within a single country, even a
culturally heterogeneous and pluralistic country such as the United States.
How do we
identify the moral commonalities or shared values that constitute a foundation
on which American institutions of higher education can build consensus, while
recognizing that the shared moral values often come into conflict with each
other and that individuals and subcultures create different hierarchies among
them? One important source of a common core of values for American higher
education derives from the responsibility to educate for citizenship that most institutions
acknowledge, even when it does not shape their practices to any significant
degree. This responsibility is clear in public institutions. But even private
colleges and universities receive public support, if only by virtue of their
tax-exempt status, and almost all college and university mission statements
refer to their responsibility to educate for leadership and contribution to
society. The responsibility to prepare citizens for participation in a
democratic system implies that some values, including some moral values,
ought to be represented in these institutions’ educational goals. These values
include mutual respect and tolerance, concern for the rights and welfare of
individuals and the community, recognition that each individual is part of the
larger social fabric, and a commitment to civil and rational discourse and
procedural impartiality.
Universities’
educational and scholarly missions also entail a set of core values. Few would
dispute that higher education ought to embody the values of intellectual
integrity and concern for truth. The academic enterprise would be fatally
compromised if these values ceased to guide scholarship, teaching, and
learning, however imperfect the guidance may be in practice. Equally central to
an institution of scholarship and higher education are the ideals of
open-mindedness, willingness to listen to and take seriously the ideas of
others, and ongoing public discussion of contested issues.
Beyond
this generic set of core values derived from the civic and intellectual
purposes of higher education, some private colleges (and even a few public)
stand for more specific moral, cultural, or religious values. The particular
missions of these institutions and their implications for their educational
programs must be made clear to prospective students and faculty. The most
obvious examples are religiously affiliated colleges and universities that
offer faith-based education in many denominations.Amongpublic institutions,
military academies are mandated to educate military officers, so their values
are defined in reference to this goal. Other public colleges were established
to serve particular populations, such as (American Indian) tribal colleges,
which often explicitly acknowledge special values such as traditional tribal
values in their curricula and programs.
If the
values on which there is broad consensus within an institution are taken
seriously, they constitute strong guiding principles for programs of moral and
civic development in higher education. Even so, they leave open to debate the
application of these principles to many particular situations. Especially in
institutions that stand for a commitment to rational public discourse, as
higher education must, discussion of the most difficult questions of
conflicting values can and should be left open to debate. Moral and civic education
provides the tools for such debate. This means that we need not begin with
agreement on the most difficult and controversial cases of conflict between
values. This makes it possible to reach a consensus on the initial set of core
values.
Some critics
may agree that, in principle, this approach to undergraduate education would be
a good thing, but fear that in practice moral and civic education programs
carry unacknowledged political and ideological baggage. These fears come from
all points on the political spectrum, with terms like morality and character
raising concerns about conservative influences and references to social justice
or social change eliciting fears of liberal political agendas. It is important
to be vigilant against educational practices that suppress a diversity of
perspectives, and when abuses occur, it is both ethically and educationally indefensible.
In my experience, however, most people engaged in college-level moral and civic
education are aware of these risks and careful to guard against abuses.
In a
project of the Carnegie Foundation for the Advancement of Teaching, several
colleagues and I visited colleges and universities of all sorts that have made
moral and civic education a priority, and have reviewed the work of many more.
In our visits to even the most specialized institutions, we were surprised by
the consistency with which faculty took care to ensure that multiple points of
view were heard, and encouraged students to question and think through the
assumptions in the dominant institutional culture. At Messiah College, a
strongly Christian college of the Brethren in Christ Church, students often
enter college not having questioned their faith and with little experience of people
from other denominations. The faculty, who are charged with helping students
explore the relationship between reason and faith, try to shake students up,
encourage them to think for themselves, and push them out of their comfort
zone. At the United States Air Force Academy, students understand that their
future roles as military officers are subject to militarycommandand military
law, but they are also taught to disobey unlawful orders. This means that
cadets have to develop the capacity for mature, independent judgment in complex
and ambiguous situations, even within the military chain of command. At
Portland State University, an urban institution in the politically liberal city
of Portland, Oregon, faculty teaching service-learning courses meet regularly
to talk about how to make sure all voices are heard in their discussions of moral,
political, and policy issues.
Every
institution we visited shares a central concern for student capacities inimical
to any effort to impose a particular party line. These capacities include
openness to reason, ability to communicate effectively, tolerance of
perspectives different from one’s own, clarity of thought and critical
thinking, and capacity for moral discourse across points of view. With the
exception of honor codes that require adherence to standards of honesty, the
central pedagogies and other programs intended to foster moral and civic
responsibility in these institutions are self-consciously noncoercive. In part
because they are encouraged to think independently, the students we observed
did not appear reluctant to resist if they thought a faculty member or another
student was trying to impose his or her views. There may be abuses of these
principles by individual faculty, or by institutions that we did not review,
but this kind of abuse can occur whether the development of students’ moral and
civic responsibility are explicit goals of the institution or not. Urging institutions
of higher education to be explicit and self-conscious in these efforts, to open
their educational practices to public view, and to join a national conversation
about these practices with a diverse range of other institutions is more likely
to minimize the abuses of power the critics fear than is attempting to run a
value-free institution. If pursued thoughtfully, an approach that brings these
issues into public debate and discussion should allow us to reappropriate words
such as morality, character, patriotism, and social justice across ideological
lines and open communication about what they mean and what their implications
are for difficult contemporary social issues.
The irony
in the charge that moral and civic education imposes arbitrary values on
students is that these values-based goals of liberal education are the best
protection from indoctrination throughout life. Helping students develop the
capacity for critical thinking, teaching them to be open-minded and interested
in pursuing ideas, requiring them to back up their claims and to expect others
to do the same, and encouraging them to be knowledgeable and accustomed to thinking
about moral, civic, and political issues puts them in the strongest position to
think independently about their positions and commitments. The more they think
about these things and learn to argue them through, the less susceptible they
are to indoctrination.
Another
common set of objections to moral and civic education at the college level is
that college students are now more likely to be seen as adults than they were
in the early to mid-twentieth century. As higher education has become
accessible to a larger segment of the population, the profile of college
students has changed. The dominant template of pre-World War II higher
education was private institutions educating full-time students from affluent
families in residential settings. This is now a small sector of American
undergraduate education. Currently, more than three out of four undergraduates
are commuter students.5 A near-majority
of undergraduates today do not come to college or university directly from high
school. They are older than their predecessors, work part-time, and are
part-time undergraduates. Many are married and are parents. These important
realities need to be taken into account as we design college-level programs to
foster moral and civic responsibility.
This
growing age diversity joins another trend toward recognizing college students’
adult status. Until the early 1970s, many residential colleges and universities
operated in loco parentis, that is, were charged with acting in a parental role
toward their students by the imposition of parietal hours and rules over a wide
range of other behavioral issues. A central purpose of this quasi-parental role
was to ensure students’ compliance with social and moral norms. As students in
the 1960s and 1970s became more politicized, they demanded treatment as adults
and much greater autonomy and self-regulation. Within less than a decade, there
were few campuses on which the policies of in loco parentis were still in
effect. This shift, along with the growing diversity in their ages and life
situations, means that for many purposes, undergraduate students are now
generally considered to be adults rather than adolescents.6
This has
led critics to argue that by the time students are in college it is too late to
affect their values and character, since moral character is assumed to be
already fully established by then. There is clear research evidence that this
assumption is incorrect. First, with reference to traditional undergraduates of
ages eighteen to twenty-two or so, all of the major developmental theorists
point to this period, which is often considered to represent the transition to
adulthood, as a time of great moral and ideological exploration, ferment, and
consolidation.7 At this time in their lives, young people question their
epistemological, moral, political, and religious assumptions, make critical
career and other life choices, and rethink their sense of who they are and what
is important to them. There could hardly be a time more ripe for moral growth.
For older
students, the relevant psychological literature is the extensive work done in
recent decades on adult and life span development. Although experiences in
childhood and adolescence are clearly important in shaping individuals’ moral
judgment, identities, and behavior, it is clear that for many people moral
development continues well into adulthood. The most sophisticated level of
moral thinking in Kohlberg’s developmental scheme, postconventional moral
judgment, does not occur until early adulthood and continues to increase at
least until the end of formal education, even beyond, for those people who
continue to participate in activities that challenge their moral thinking.8
Parallel
findings emerge from studies of moral identity and behavior. In a study of
highly committed moral exemplars, William Damon and I found that many of these
individuals did not exhibit the exceptional commitment that came to
characterize their lives until well into adulthood.9 For example,
we wrote about a woman who was a selfdescribed racist into her thirties who
became a leader in the black civil rights movement in her late thirties and
early forties through a series of transformative experiences that took place
over several years. Similarly, we described a businessman who was financially
successful, but rather unremarkable from the moral point of view, who became a
tireless advocate for the poor in middle age, establishing and devoting much of
his time and energy to a program that provides a broad range of services to
low-income people in the Roanoke Valley of Virginia.
Even if
it is possible for people to develop morally in adulthood, some would say that
it is presumptuous for institutions of higher education to try to affect the moral
understanding and behavior of adult students. In response to this objection, I
ask whether it is presumptuous to help undergraduate students think more
clearly about challenging moral dilemmas, engage in an intellectually serious
way the moral issues that arise in academic disciplines, and participate in
service to the community, reflecting on what is learned in the process. And is
it presumptuous to ask them to adhere to high ethical standards regarding academic
integrity and other issues of honesty and mutual respect within the campus
community, become interested in and knowledgeable about contemporary social,
policy, and political issues, participate in public discourse and debate
regarding campus and community issues, and take advantage of opportunities to
act on their most cherished beliefs? Understood in this way, it would seem that
moral and civic education is appropriate not only to adults who are attending
college but to all adults. Public lectures, community forums, public radio and television,
church and political party membership, cultural events such as theater and
museum exhibits, self-help groups such as Alcoholics Anonymous, and interest
groups that discuss books and films all provide continuing opportunities for
moral and civic growth for adults who are well past their college years. I
would go so far as to argue that every institution of society that attempts to
deepen individual and collective understanding, including the media, religion,
and the arts, has a responsibility to foster moral and civic learning.
Another
objection to undergraduate moral and civic education derives from the tendency
discussed earlier to see higher education as a commodity purchased by students
as an investment in their future earning power. The argument is that students
are consumers who want to buy occupational preparation, not moral and civic
education. It is true that students (and their parents) consider career
preparation the primary purpose of their undergraduate education, even at small
liberal arts colleges.10 Moreover,
the overwhelming majority of undergraduates major in a particular discipline
because they believe it provides the quickest, safest route to highly paid
employment, which has made business the number one major at American colleges
and universities.
Clearly,
vocational preparation is a valid and important goal of higher education, but
vocational preparation need not compete with or be disconnected from other
goals. Institutions of higher education are wellsituated to encourage students
to think about a vocation as something larger and potentially far richer than
simple careerism. The special nature of colleges and universities as
intellectual communities gives them opportunities to embed the occupational
goals of students in a broader and more socially meaningful framework.
Vocational
preparation should not be treated as an endeavor that is distinct from growth
in moral and civic responsibility. Work is central to the lives of most adults,
a primary domain in which we have the opportunity to contribute to the welfare
of others or to the community more broadly. Work is also one of the two or
three most important places where we seek meaning in our lives.11 For these
reasons, it is important to integrate into any educational program a concern
for ethical and socially responsible occupational practices and to place students’
understanding of their occupation in a larger social and intellectual context
for deeper meaning. In effect, higher education can help turn occupations into
callings, and they will be better for it.
A
question often raised about undergraduate moral and civic education is whether
academic learning suffers if faculty broaden their educational goals in this
way. If it is to be effective, this work must be intellectually rigorous and
programmatically powerful. In our investigations of curricular and
extracurricular programs of moral and civic education, we see many that meet
the highest standards of quality. As in other areas of higher education, we
also see weak programs. To ensure that this uneven quality does not
short-change and alienate students or detract from the credibility of the
enterprise, programs of moral and civic education need tough-minded scrutiny
even when their goals are unimpeachable. We also need to develop creative tools
for assessment research to demonstrate good programs’ quality to the range of
interested publics and provide the kind of information that will improve ineffective
programs.
We
believe that this research can demonstrate that the best programs actually have
a positive impact on academic learning as well as on moral and civic
responsibility. In an evaluation of a large number of service learning
programs, Alexander Astin and his colleagues found significant positive effects
of participation in service-learning on grade point average, writing skills,
and critical thinking skills, as well as commitment to community service,
self-efficacy, and leadership ability.12
Eyler and
Giles report research indicating that students’ academic performance and
self-assessment of their own learning and motivation increases through
participation in high quality service-learning programs, especially those that
involve challenging service work well integrated with the course material and
accompanied by opportunities for structured reflection on their service
experience.13 On the other hand, this research shows that the weaker service-learning
experiences do not have these positive results. Clearly, quality matters, so we
need to develop the tools both to evaluate and ensure the highest quality in all
this work.
It is
clear that students’ values, moral and civic assumptions, and identities are
shaped in college. It is time to be more self-conscious and intentional about
this, and to think carefully about the particular framing of goals and
strategies that are appropriate and feasible within a given institution. It is
also important that faculty and administrators doing this kind of work document
what they are doing and make it public so that it can be shared and discussed.
This will open specific practices to critique and allow institutions to learn
from their own and others’ experience. Public scrutiny of these programs is a
safeguard against practices that overstep the bounds of what is legitimate and
will allow us to develop further the local and national discourse about what should
be done and how best to accomplish it. This discourse can also help faculty and
students think through dilemmas that arise in moral and civic education on
college campuses, such as the tension between spirited debate and concern for
others’ feelings.
There are
many approaches to fostering students’ moral and civic responsibility in
American higher education. Different conceptions of the goals and different
programs of activity, both curricular and extracurricular, are appropriate to
different kinds of institutions. A military academy will conceive of its
specific goals quite differently from a community college on an Indian
reservation; a nonresidential, public, urban university will have a very
different approach from that of a small, religiously affiliated liberal arts
college. It is important for each institution to build on the best of its own
traditions and history as it creates new initiatives. In spite of this
diversity, however, there are some common principles that underlie effective
moral and civic education, and even institutions that are very different have a
great deal to learn from each other.
First,
the intellectual core of moral and civic development is critical. This includes
not only critical thinking and the capacity to reason about moral and political
issues in a sophisticated way (as described developmentally by Kohlberg and
others), but also includes deep understanding of many content domains,
including our political and economic systems, the fundamentals of ethical
concepts in philosophy, and a grasp of American historical and cultural
legacies as related to the global context. These are the traditional domains of
a liberal arts education, with clear links to moral and civic development.
Second,
educators must recognize that cognitive or intellectual dimensions cannot be
separated from the dimensions of personal meaning, affect, and motivation in
moral and civic education, or in general education. Any effort to focus on the
narrowly intellectual alone is selfdefeating because it does not result in
lasting learning. Ideally, moral and civic education at the college level, as
at younger ages, should take a holistic approach that affects the entire
environment and its moral atmosphere, creating a campus climate among
administration, faculty, and student peer culture that supports the education
of the whole person around a core set of shared moral and intellectual
concerns. This best ensures the development of routines of moral interpretation
and habits of behavior grounded in trustworthiness, mutual respect,
open-mindedness, concern for the welfare of others, and active, thoughtful
citizenship.
A
holistic, multi-faceted approach is especially conducive to creating an
enduring identity that incorporates moral and civic concerns. We know this is
the key to a strength of commitment that withstands the inevitable challenges
that moral and civic engagement entail. In our study of moral exemplars who
sustained exceptional levels of moral commitment over many decades, Bill Damon
and I were interested to see that these people did not make sharp distinctions
among their personal, professional, and moral goals. Instead, they defined
themselves through their moral goals and fully integrated what they wanted personally
with what they thought was right. Cabell Brand, the businessman who developed
anti-poverty programs around Roanoke, Virginia, expressed his sense of moral
and personal integration when I asked, “When you think about these moral goals
and values and so on, how do these relate to your sense of who you are as a
person?” He responded, “Well, it’s one and the same. Who I am is what I’m able
to do and how I feel all the time—each day, each moment . . . It’s hard for me
to separate who I amfrom what I want to do and what I amdoing [in these
programs].”14 Mother Waddles, an African-American woman who established a mission for
the low-income communities of Detroit, sounded remarkably like Brand, the
wealthy white entrepreneur. In talking about the stability of her commitment to
this work, she said, “Because I didn’t promise that I would do it contingent
upon what kind of building, what kind of clothes I could wear, what kind of
money I had; just as long as I can find something I can do, I’ll do it. So no
matter where I am going, people can at least know to pinpoint me in what category
I’m in. Without even asking, ‘I know wherever she is, if she’s alive and well,
she’s a missionary.’ So I think that’s my greatest achievement—to find yourself
and know who you are, and get joy out of being you.”15
People at
this high level of commitment have found ways to integrate the things that
inspire them and the things they want to accomplish and to build these into
their core sense of who they are. This results not only in outstanding service
to others but also in an exceptional degree of personal well-being and
fulfillment for the exemplars themselves. Many people never achieve this level
of personal integration. Developing a fully integrated life is one of the most
challenging psychological tasks of adulthood. In older forms, which often began
from a spiritual base and treated one’s life work as a calling, this was
accepted as a legitimate part of the agenda for higher education. It is now
time to redefine this earlier vision in a contemporary framework and hold
colleges and universities accountable for a fuller conception of the educated person.
1.
Lawrence Kohlberg, “Indoctrination and Relativity in Value Education,” Xygon 6 (1971):
285–309; P. W. Jackson, Life in the Classroom (New
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1968); G. D. Fenstermacher, “Some Moral Considerations
on Teaching as a Profession,” in J. Goodlad, R. Soder, and K. Sirotnik, eds., The Moral
Dimensions of Teaching (San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass, 1990): 130–54.
2. For a
discussion of these issues in the field of economics, see Myra H. Strober, “Rethinking
Economics through a Feminist Lens,” American Economic Review (May 1994):
143–47.
3. See,
for example: J. Rest, Development in Judging
Moral Issues (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1979); M. J. Bebeau, “Influencing the Moral Dimension of Dental Practice,” in
J. Rest and D. Narvaez, eds., Moral Development in the
Professions (Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Press,
1994); J. Walker, “Choosing Biases, Using Power and Practicing Resistance:
Moral Development in a World without Certainty,” Human Development 43:3(2000):
135–94.
4. R.
Shweder, “True Ethnography: The Lore, the Law, and the Lure,” in R. Jessor, A.
Colby, and R. Shweder, eds., Ethnography and Human
Development (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996):
15–52.
5. U.S.
Bureau of the Census, Statistical Abstract of the United
States: 1998, 118th ed. (Springfield, Va.: National Technical Information
Services, 1998).
6. We
recognize that, especially since the passage of the GI Bill after World War II,
there have always been some older students in American colleges and
universities. Even so, until the last several decades the dominant image of
college students in the public mind has been that of young people not yet
prepared to take responsibility for themselves. Some influential psychological
theorists such as Erik Erikson and Marcia called this period a “moratorium”
between adolescence and adulthood. See E. Erikson, Identity, Youth and Crisis (New
York: Norton, 1968) and J. E. Marcia, “Identity in Adolescence,” in J. Adelson,
ed., Handbook of Adolescent Psychology (New York: Wiley, 1980).
7. E.
Erikson, Identity, Youth, and Crisis (New York: Norton, 1968);
William Perry, Jr. Forms of Intellectual and
Ethical Development in the College Years (New York: Holt, Rinehart,
and Winston, 1968); Lawrence Kohlberg, The Psychology of Moral
Development (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1984); J.
Loevinger, Ego Development (San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass, 1976).
8. A.
Colby, L. Kohlberg, J. Gibbs and M. Lieberman, “A Longitudinal Study of Moral
Judgment,” Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 48:1– 2
(1983). J. Rest, D. Narvaez, M. Bebeau, and S. Thoma, Postconventional
Moral Thinking (Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1999).
9. A.
Colby and W. Damon, Some Do Care: Contemporary
Lives of Moral Commitment (New York: Free Press,
1992).
10. R. H.
Hersh and D. Yankelovich, “Intentions and Perceptions: A National Survey of
Public Attitudes toward Liberal Arts Education,” Change 29:2(1997):
16–23.
11. A.
Colby, L. Sippola, and E. Phelps, “Social Responsibility and Paid Work in
Contemporary American Life,” in A. Ross, ed., Caring and Doing for
Others: Social Responsibility in the Domains of Family, Work, and Community (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, in press).
12. A.
Astin, L. Vogelgesang, E. Ikeda, and J. Yee, “How Service Learning Affects
Students: Executive Summary” (Los Angeles: Higher Education Research Institute,
UCLA, January, 2000). Retrieved June 1, 2000, from http://www.gseis.ucla.edu/slc/
rhowas.html.
13. J.
Eyler and D. Giles, Where’s the Learning in
Service-Learning? (San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass, 1999).
14. See
Colby and Damon (1992): 304.
15.
Ibid., 218.
==============================
Irving
Kristol
I have been
asked to write about moral and ethical development in a democratic
society, and I should like to express my discomfort with that term
“development.” It is such a curious word, so tantalizingly neutral and
therefore so ambiguous in defining our relation to morality. After all, the
title could easily have been “moral and ethical education in a democratic
society.” Why wasn’t it? Well, I assume the reason is that we are not certain
that it is a proper function of education to shape young people according to
any specific set of moral standards, and the term “moral education” does imply
an activity of that sort. Development, on the other hand, suggests that
morality is something that exists embryonically within every child—rather like
an intelligence quotient—and that education’s purpose is to encourage it to
unfold toward its fullest potential. Morality, in this view, is something that
happens to one, so education then becomes a process of liberating human
possibilities for this eventual happening rather than of defining human possibilities
in an approved way.
This is
certainly a very convenient notion for teachers or all those in a position of
authority, because it means that they need not have any firm
moral beliefs or provide a moral model of any kind. The process of development
can then be regarded as a purely technical problem—of means, not of ends—and
the solution is to get people, especially young people, to have feelings about
morality and to think about it: to be morally sensitive and morally aware, as
we say. Once this has been successfully accomplished, the task of education is
finished. What kinds of people emerge from this process is something we can
leave to the people themselves freely to decide; the final disposition of their
moral sentiments and ideas is their business, not anyone else’s.
It’s all
very odd and most interesting, rather as if an expert in gardening were to
compose a manual on botanical development in a suburban landscape. He would
give you all sorts of important information on how things grow—weeds as well as
flowers, poison ivy as well as roses—without ever presuming to tell you whether
you should favor one over the other, or how to favor
one over the other. In fact, there are no such gardening manuals, precisely
because any gardener has some definite ideas about how a garden might look.
Different gardeners have different ideas, of course; but there is a limit to
this variety. The idea of a garden does not, for instance, include an expanse of
weeds or poison ivy, and no gardener would ever confuse a garden with a garbage
dump.
In
contrast, we seem unable or unwilling to establish defining limits to the idea
of a moral person. We are, as it were, gardeners with all the latest implements
and technology, but without an idea of a garden. Is this a function of mere
ignorance? Or mere timidity? I think not. Rather, we have faith in the nature
of people that we do not have in the botanical processes of nature itself, and
I use the word “faith” in its full religious force. We really do believe that
all human beings have a natural telos toward
becoming flowers, not weeds or poison ivy, and that in the aggregate human
beings have a natural predisposition to arrange themselves into gardens, not
jungles or garbage heaps. This sublime and noble faith we may call the religion
of liberal humanism. It is the dominant spiritual and intellectual orthodoxy in
America today. Indeed, despite all our chatter about the separation of church
and state, one can even say it is the official religion of American society
today, compared wit which all other religions can be criticized as divisive and
parochial.
I happen
not to be a believer in this religion of liberal humanism, but this is not the
time or place for theological controversy and I am not, in any case, the
best-qualified person for such a controversy. I shall simply remark on what I
take to be a fact: Though the majority of the American people may well
subscribe to some version of this religion—and I think they do—the young among
us end up holding in contempt all the institutions in which the ethos of this
religion is incarnated. Indeed, incredibly, they become increasingly alienated
from these institutions, and end up feeling that these institutions are in some
way unresponsive and irrelevant to their basic needs. Their parents soon echo
these complaints.
What I
suggest is that the moral neutrality of our institutions, especially our
educational institutions, robs them of their popular legitimacy. Nor does it
matter if this moral neutrality is, at the moment, popularly approved of and
sanctioned by public opinion. It still deprives these institutions of their
legitimacy. One does not have to be a particularly keen student of history or
psychology to know that people will accept, tolerate, or even praise
institutions which later will suddenly be experienced as intolerable and
unworthy. Institutions, like worm-eaten trees, can look healthy and imposing
until they crumble overnight into the dust. If you look at the cahiers submitted
to the French Assembly on the eve of the great revolution, you find not a
breath of dissatisfaction with the monarchy—not a hint of republican
aspirations. Similarly, early in 1964, an opinion poll among students at the
University of California at Berkeley found that the overwhelming majority
thought very well of the school and believed they were getting an excellent education
there. Nevertheless, both Louis XVI and Clark Kerr soon found themselves riding
the whirlwind. Such abrupt eruptions of profound discontent catch us all by
surprise, whether we are talking about the rebelliousness of racial minorities,
or young people, or women, or whomever. They are characteristic of American
society today and also characteristic of a society whose institutions—whether
they be political institutions, or schools, or the family—are being drained of
their legitimacy—of their moral acceptance, for that is what legitimacy means.
We try to
cope with this problem by incessantly restructuring our institutions to make
them more responsive to popular agitation, but that obviously does not work
very well. The more we fiddle around with our schools, the more energetically
we restructure and then re-restructure them according to the passing fancy of
intellectual fashion, the more steadily do they lose their good repute. One can
only conclude that either there is something wrong with the idea of
responsiveness as we currently understand it, or that there is some fault in
our idea of the people as we currently understand it. I suggest that there is
something wrong with both of these ideas as we currently understand them.
Ultimately, we are talking about a single error rather than a dual one: an error
in the way we conceive the relations between a people and their institutions in
a democratic society.
There is
an old Groucho Marx chestnut about how he resigned from a club immediately upon
being elected to membership, his resignation prompted by the thought that any
club that would elect him a member couldn’t possibly be worth joining. I think
that, in this old chestnut, there is a lesson for all of us about
responsiveness. More and more of our institutions have been reaching out for
greater participation and involvement, and an ever-larger number of those new
recruits to full membership in the club have been busy resigning.
It is not
easy to say to what degree our various strategies of responsiveness are
motivated by sly cunning or plain self-deception. In the heyday of campus
protest over the Vietnam war, amidst an upsurge of general political radicalism
among college students, Congress decided to lower the voting age to eighteen.
To the best of my knowledge, there was not a single protest meeting on any
American campus on the issue of a lower voting age. Similarly, to the best of
my knowledge, Congress did not receive a single mass petition on this matter
from young people. Nevertheless, Congress decided that, in the face of unrest,
it couldn’t simply remain mute and impassive, so it decided to be responsive in
its way. It didn’t end the Vietnam war or abolish capitalism, but instead passed
a constitutional amendment lowering the voting age to eighteen. That amendment
was promptly ratified by the requisite number of state legislatures, and
shortly thereafter Richard Nixon was elected President by an overwhelming
majority of the popular vote.
One of
the ways in which we characteristically respond is to give dissatisfied people
what they have not asked for, what there was never any sound reason for believing
they really wanted. Thus, when nonwhites in the ghettos of New York City began
to express dissatisfaction with the fact that their children graduated from
high school without even being able to read or reckon at an elementary school
level, they were promptly given community control over their local school
boards and open admissions to the senior city colleges, but if you look back at
the course of events, you will discover that there never was any real popular
demand as distinct from political–demagogicdemand for either community control
or open admissions. Neither had any bearing on the problems at hand. As a
matter of fact, any authentic conception of community control stood in rank
contradiction to the practice of busing students for purposes of integration,
which was also under way in New York’s schools.
We are
responsive in another seemingly more candid, but actually even more cunning,
way. This is to give people what they actually demand—or what some vociferously
demand—in the tranquil knowledge that because these demands are misconceived,
their satisfaction is a meaningless gesture. That is what has happened with
parietal rules, course gradings, class attendance, curriculum requirements,
nominal student representation on various committees, and so forth, on so many of
our college campuses, as well as in lower schools. The strategy may be defined
as follows. When confronted with protest, dissatisfaction, and tumult, unburden
yourself of your responsibilities but keep all your privileges, then announce
that your institution has enlarged the scope of participation and freedom for
all constituents. Since participation and freedom are known to be good
democratic things, you have the appearance of rectitude and the reality of
survival.
This
complicated game of responsiveness has been skillfully played these past years
and has enabled a great many institutions to secure their imperiled positions.
In that sense, it has been unquestionably successful. In a deeper sense,
however, it has gained nothing but time—a precious enough gain, but only if one
realizes that it is simply time that has been gained, and that this time must
be used productively if the gain is to be substantial rather than illusory. It
is not my impression that any such realization exists.
Through
the ages political philosophers and educators have argued that it is unwise to
give people rights without, at the same time, imposing obligations—that rights
without obligations make for irresponsibility, just as obligations without
rights make for servility. Edmund Burke pushed this thesis further when he
declared that it was part of the people’s rights to have obligations—that an
absence of obligation means a diminution of humanity because it signifies a
condition of permanent immaturity.Wecan extend this line of thought even
further and declare with confidence, based on our own more recent experience,
that obligation is not only a right but a need. People upon whom no obligations
are imposed will experience an acute sense of deprivation. It is our striking
failure to recognize this phenomenon of moral deprivation for what it is that
explains our fumbling, cynical response to the dissatisfaction that Americans
express toward their institutions.
Institutions
that pander to citizens (I use that word “pander” advisedly) in an effort to
achieve popularity may get good press for a while. Our mass media, for which
pandering is an economic necessity, are naturally keen to see other
institutions remake themselves in the media’s own image, to become responsive
as a television station or network is responsive. Responsiveness here means to
satisfy popular appetite or desire or whim or fancy or, rather, to satisfy what
is thought at any moment to be popular appetite or desire or whim or fancy.
Such responsiveness, being timely and circumstantial, is also thought to be relevant.
But amidst the noise of mutual self-congratulation, what is lost sight of is
the fact that these institutions, floating on clouds of approval and
self-approval, have uprooted themselves from that solid ground of moral
legitimacy from which all institutions receive their long-term nourishment.
Do I
exaggerate? Well, let mecite the problems of ghetto education. During the past
decades we have had dozens of bold innovations in the schooling of slum kids,
each claiming to be more responsive and more relevant than the previous ones.
Some of these innovations have even revived forms of classroom organization and
techniques of pedagogy that were popular a hundred years ago, and you can’t be
more innovative than that! Each innovation, at some moment, is held up as a
breakthrough, is the subject of enthusiastic magazine articles and television reports,
is quickly imitated by enterprising school administrators elsewhere, and is
generally judged to be a success before any results are in.
Then it
quietly vanishes, and nothing more is heard about it as attention shifts to
some later innovation, by some other bold educational reformer who has broken
through encrusted tradition and has come up with an even more responsive and
relevant program. Meanwhile, back in the ghetto, there exists a whole set of
successful schools that no one pays any attention to—schools successful in the
most elementary yet crucial terms: A long list of parents try desperately to register
their children in these schools; the truancy and transfer rates are low, there
is less juvenile delinquency and a lower rate of drug addiction among all
students, and academic achievement levels tend to be slightly higher than
average. I refer to the parochial schools in the ghetto, which no one writes
about, which the media ignore, but which—in the opinion of parents and students
alike—are the most desirable of all ghetto schools. Many of these parochial
schools are in old buildings with minimal facilities—a pitiful library perhaps,
a squalid gymnasium perhaps, a Spartan lunchroom perhaps. Anyone who ever takes
the trouble to open his or her eyes to the existence of these schools is not
taken aback—as so many were—by the findings of the Coleman report that the
condition or even nonexistence of such physical facilities had little
connection with educational achievement.
Why are
the parochial schools in the ghetto so well regarded? The answer is obvious:
They are self-respecting institutions, demanding institutions, with standards
that students are expected to meet. Many of them enforce dress codes as a
symbolic gesture of self-affirmation. By making such demands upon their
students, they cause them to make demands upon themselves and, most important, cause
their students to realize that the only true moral and intellectual
“development” occurs when you do make demands upon yourself.
I suppose
that what I am saying can and will be interpreted as just another critique of
what we call permissiveness. I should be unhappy if this happens, because I so
intensely dislike both that term and its associations. People who
indiscriminately attack permissiveness are themselves victims of confusion
between authority and authoritarianism—a confusion they share with the very
tendencies they criticize. Permissiveness and authoritarianism are two possible
poles of moral discourse.
Both of
them are poles that come into existence when the center no longer holds. That
center is authority, meaning the exercise of power toward some morally affirmed
end in such a reasonable way as to secure popular acceptance. Legitimate
authority is not always reasonable, since it is exercised by people who are not
always naturally reasonable. No one is always reasonable, and therefore
legitimate authority is open to criticism and correction. But if authority may
be flawed in operation, both permissiveness and authoritarianism are flawed in
their morally void and substanceless goals. This second flaw is clearly
infinitely more important than the first. It induces a kind of technocratic
mania, with exponents of permissiveness devising ever-new ways of liberating
the citizen, with no idea as to what he is being liberated for, while exponents
of authoritarianism are busy learning how to control people solely to secure
the power of existing institutions, with no serious conception about the
ultimate purpose of this power.
Properly
understood, authority is to be distinguished from power, which is the capacity
to coerce. In the case of authority, power is not experienced as coercive
because it is infused, however dimly, with a moral intention that corresponds
to the moral sentiments and moral ideals of those who are subject to this
power. Education, in its only significant sense, is such an exercise in
legitimate authority. When educators say that they don’t know what their moral
intention is, that they don’t know what kinds of human beings they are trying
to create, they have surrendered all claim to legitimate authority. Moral
development, as now conceived in our schools of education, is never associated with
ultimate mental intentions. (That would be authoritarian.)
As a
result, what we call moral development can easily give rise to moral deprivation—a
hunger of the soul for moral meanings—which is far more devastating and
dangerous than physical hunger. In the end, this hunger of the soul will
satisfy itself by gratefully submitting to any passing pseudoauthority. But
where on earth, in this bewildered age, are our educators going to discover
this moral authority without which authentic education is impossible? Who is
going to answer questions about the meaning of our individual and collective
lives? I recognize both the cogency and poignancy of this lament: Ours is
indeed a bewildered age. I would say this: If you have no sense of moral
authority, if you have no sovereign ideas about moral purpose, you ought not to
be educators. There are many technocratic professions in which, for all practical
purposes, the knowledge of means suffices, but education is not one of them. An
educator who cannot give at least a tentative, minimally coherent reply to the
question, “Education for what?” and who cannot at least point to the kinds of
persons a good education is supposed to produce, is simply in the wrong line of
work. It is my impression that, in fact, most educators, being sincerely
committed to the educational enterprise, are in the right kind of work. Most do
know more than they feel free to admit about the aim of education to achieve this
freedom as one of the major purposes of education reform today.
==============================
Marvin W.
Berkowitz, Sanford N. McDonnell Professor of Character Education at the
University of Missouri-St. Louis, has served as Ambassador Holland H. Coors
Professor of Character Development at the United States Air Force Academy and
professor of psychology and founder and director of the Center for Ethics
Studies at Marquette University. He is a developmental psychologist interested
in child and adolescent development, moral thinking, and character education,
with special interests in moral conflict discussion, adolescent risk-taking, parenting,
and substance abuse.
Anne
Colby joined the Carnegie Foundation for the Advancement of Teaching as a
senior scholar in 1997. Prior to that, she was director of the Henry Murray
Research Center at Harvard University, a longitudinal studies data archive and
social science research center. She is the principal author of A
Longitudinal Study of Moral Judgment (1983)
and The Measurement of Moral Judgment (1987),
co-author with William Damon of Some Do Care: Contemporary
Lives of Moral Commitment (1992), and coeditor of Ethnography
and HumanDevelopment: Context and
Meaning in HumanInquiry (1995), and Competence
and Character through Life (1998). At the Carnegie
Foundation, she is codirector of the Preparation for the Professions Program
and the Project on Higher Education and the Development of Moral and Civic
Responsibility.
William
Damon is Professor of Education and Director of the Center on Adolescence at
Stanford University. He received his Ph.D. in developmental psychology from
University of California at Berkeley. Damon’s books include Self-understanding
in Childhood and Adolescence (1988); The Moral
Child (1990); Some Do Care: Contemporary Lives of Moral
Commitment (1992); Greater
Expectations (1995); and, most recently, The Youth
Charter: How Communities Can Work Together to Raise Standards for All Our
Children (1997). Damon is editor-in-chief of New
Directions for Child Development and The
Handbook of Child Psychology. He has been elected to
membership in the National Academy of Education. Damon is a Hoover Institution
senior fellow.
Amitai
Etzioni is the first university professor of The George Washington University.
He is the author of twenty-one books, including The Monochrome
Society (Princeton: Princeton University Press, April 2001), Next: The
Road to the Good Society (New York: Basic Books, January
2001), The Limits of Privacy (New York: Basic Books,
Spring 1999), and The New Golden Rule:
Community and Morality in a Democratic Society (New
York: Basic Books, 1996), which received the Simon Wiesenthal Center’s 1997
Tolerance Book Award. He is also editor of The
Responsive Community: Rights and Responsibilities, a communitarian
quarterly.
Irving
Kristol is coeditor of The Public Interest magazine,
John M. Olin Distinguished Fellow at the American Enterprise Institute, a
fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, and a lifetime member of
the Council on Foreign Relations. He is the author of Neoconservatism:
The Autobiography of an Idea (1995), Reflections
of a Neoconservative (1983), Two
Cheers for Capitalism (1978), and On the Democratic
Idea in America (1972).
F.
Clark Power is a professor in the Program of Liberal Studies, concurrent professor
of psychology, and fellow of the Institute for Educational Initiatives at the
University of Notre Dame. He also serves as the associate director for academic
affairs and research for the Mendelson Center for Sports, Character, and
Culture. He received an Ed.D. in Human Development from Harvard’s Graduate
School of Education in 1979. His research and writing focus on moral
development and democratic education. He is a coauthor of The
Measurement of Moral Judgment, Vol. II: Standard Issue Scoring Manual, and Lawrence
Kohlberg’s Approach to Moral Education; he is
also coeditor of Self, Ego and Identity: Integrative
Approaches; The Challenge of Pluralism: Education, Politics and Values; and Character
Psychology and Character Education (forthcoming).
Arthur
J. Schwartz has directed the character development programs for the John Templeton
Foundation since 1995. He also serves as project director for the Foundation’s
popular guidebook Colleges That Encourage
Character Development. He received his doctorate
from Harvard University.
Nancy
Sherman is university professor of philosophy at Georgetown University. In
1997–99, she served as the inaugural holder of the Distinguished Chair in
Ethics at the United States Naval Academy. She has been an associate professor
of philosophy at Yale University and has held visiting positions at Johns
Hopkins and the University of Maryland. She is the author of The
Fabric of Character (Oxford University Press, 1989)
and Making a Necessity of Virtue (Cambridge
University Press, 1997) and the editor of Critical
Essays on the Classics: Aristotle’s Ethics (Rowman
and Littlefield, 1999). She has written over thirty published articles in the
general area of ethics and moral psychology. Professor Sherman holds a Ph.D.
from Harvard University in philosophy (1982).
Christina
Hoff Sommers is a resident scholar at the American Enterprise Institute in
Washington, D.C. She is the author of The War Against
Boys and Who Stole Feminism?
Lawrence
J. Walker is professor of psychology and coordinator of the graduate program at
the University of British Columbia, having received his Ph.D. from the
University of Toronto in 1978. He is past president of the Association for
Moral Education and currently serves as associate editor of the Merrill-Palmer
Quarterly. His research focuses on issues relating to the psychology of moral
development, including processes in the development of moral reasoning and the
formation of moral personality.
==============================
academic integrity standards programs: benefits
of, 16–17; growing number of, 11–12; transmitting core values through, 12–17
Achilles, 90
Achilles in Vietnam (Shay),
91
adolescent character development, 51–52
African-American cultural maxims, 8, 10n.13
African-American Proverbs
in Context (Prhalad), 7
agency: link between sense of self and,
73–74; tension between moral functioning and, 73, 82–83. See also ethics;
morality
aidos (negative
appraisal of self), 14
American Association of Higher Education, 151
American Psychiatric Association, 51
ancient Greek culture: Stoicism development in,
88–96; strong bodies/minds beliefs of, 96, 98–99
Anderson, Debbie, 125
Andreotta, Glenn, 108
anger/rage, 104–9
apprenticeship model of schools, 137
Aquinas, Thomas, 87
Arendt, Hannah, 23
Aristotelian moral education approach, 25–27,
35, 41
Aristotle, 25–27, 34, 87, 88, 98, 105, 106
Aspen Declaration on Character Education, 37–38
Association of American Colleges and Universities,
151
Astin, Alexander, 167
attachment bond development, 50, 51
Augustine, Saint, 26, 28, 29, 30
authority: authoritarianism vs., 180–81; distinguished
from power, 181–82
automony, progressive vs. directive view of,
34
Bakhtin, Mikhael, 4
Bandura, A., 75
Battistich, V. A., 57
Baumeister, Roy, 52
Bebeau, Muriel, 154
Bishop, Dorothy, 8
Blasi, A., 74
Blasi, Gus, 20
Blatt, Moshe, 132
Boston University, 41
Brand, Cabell, 170
Brothers, Christopher, 9
Brown, Lynn, 3
Buls, Verla, 125
Burke, Edmund, 178
Campus Compact, 151
Carnegie Foundation for the Advancement of Teaching,
160
Center for Academic Integrity, 11
Center for the Advancement of Ethics and Character
(Boston University), 41
character: espousing/practicing positive, 60;
as individual’s set of psychological characteristics, 48–49; new focus of moral
psychology on, 71–80; sources of, 53–55; various definitions of, 47–48
Character Counts Coalition, 37, 38
Character Counts program (Fallon Park Elementary),
38–39, 41
character development: adolescent, 52–53;
childhood, 51–52; import of experience on, 123–25;
infant and toddler, 50–51, 118–19; influence of observed treatment on, 59–60; parenting
and, 55–56; parenting styles and, 55–56; principles of, 114–15; role of moral education
in, 121–23; role of parents and society in, 53–55, 58–59, 116–17; selfcontrol acquired
through, 118–19; stages of, 49–50; treatment of child influence on, 58–59
Character Development Project, 58
Character Education Partnership, 45, 48
character education programs: absence of
“felt knowledge” in, 20–21; Aspen Declaration on Character Education principles
on, 37–38; current focus on prevention behaviors of, 11; debate over
transmission of, 3; future of, 62–63; higher education, 61–62; maxims to live
by used in, 5–10; overview of current state of, 45–47; parental involvement in,
61; research on successful, 56–58; role of discipline, self-discipline, and
internalization in, 119–21; school environment issues of, 130; summary of what
works in, 58–61; terminology of, 44–45; transmitting moral knowledge/ideals as essential
for, 2–5; value of teacher/student bonding to, 125–27; viewed as indoctrination,
2. See also moral education; schools
Child Development Project, 46, 56–57
children: Aristotle on moral development of, 26–27;
character development and treatment observed by, 59–60; character development
and treatment of, 58–59; daily practice with moral values by, 81–83; development
of character in, 49–53, 118–19; duty of society to civilize, 23–24; moral education
and autonomy of, 34; morality of constraint vs. cooperation among, 137; moral
reasoning opportunities of, 60–61; Rousseau on moral development of, 27–30
Christian doctrine: directive style of moral education
and, 30; on healing of love and compassion, 92; on human nature, 26, 28. See also religion
Chrysippus, 88
Cicero, 88–89, 95, 99, 102, 104
civic education: adult status of higher education
students and, 162–65; college vocational training vs., 165–66; conclusions regarding
higher education, 168–71; higher education approaches to, 158–62; intellectual
weakness of higher education, 167–68. See also moral
education
Cleanthes, 88
Cluster School: approach to discipline of stealing
by, 144–47; attempted adoption of madrich role in,
139; benefits of participation in, 148; community meetings held in, 135; Harvard
field trip sponsored by, 135–36; origins of, 133–34; participatory democracy
practiced in, 134–38. See also Just
Community Schools
codes of conduct: benefits of school honor, 16–17;
core values transmitted through school honor, 12–17; military linking of morality
and, 100–104
cognitive-developmental tradition, 67
“Cognitive Development Theory and the Practice
of Collective Moral Education” (Kohlberg), 133
cognitive moral development, 31–33
Colbum, Larry, 108
Colby, Anne, 78
collective norms: building community through,
143–47; challenge of identifying higher education, 158–62; defining, 144
Columbine High School massacre (1999), 35–37,
39–40
community: built through collective norms, 143–47;
school reinforcement of values held by, 116; schools within, 116–17
community service, 117
concept of persons, 50, 51
Confessions (Saint
Augustine), 29
core values: associated with moral maturity, 74–75;
challenge of identifying higher education, 158–62; debate over transmitting vs.
indoctrinating, 1–2; debate over “whose,” 1, 121–22, 155–62; as essential to
character education, 2–5, 81–83, 121–23; honor codes used to transmit, 12–17;
responsibility of conserving/transmitting, 18; school reinforcement of community,
116
Coriolanus (Shakespeare character), 90, 111
Corporation for National Service, 151
cultures: ancient Greek and Roman, 88–96, 96,
98–99; discipline that changes peer, 139, 141–42; diversity of norms in
different, 157–58; maxims of African-American, 8, 10n.13; maxims as “memory
bank” of civilized, 6; “proverb tradition” emphasized by some, 7
Damon, William, 40, 78, 122, 164, 170
Dearen, Nan, 41
demandingness parenting, 56
Democracy and Education (Dewey),
4
DeMott, Benjamin, 40
Dewey, John, 4, 18, 19, 136
Diogenes the Cynic, 92
directive style of moral education, 30–31,
33, 34
discipline: character development role by, 119–21;
influence of methods used by school, 115–16; Just Community Schools use of
peer, 143–47; “the morality of the classroom,” 139–42; Ms. Jones’s authoritarian
approach to cheating, 139–42
Discrimination Day school experiment, 124–25
Durkheim, Emile, 133
Duvall, Robert, 102
Edney, “Bud,” 97
education: civic, 158–71; institutions of ghetto,
179–80; value-neutral, 25, 116, 152–55. See also higher
education; moral education
Education Week, 36
egkrateia (self-control),
98
“Eleven Principles of Effective Character
Education” (Character Education Partnership),
45–46
Elliott, Jane, 124–25
Emile (Rousseau),
29
emotions: Aristotle’s view on responsive nature
of, 105–6; shame, 14–15; Stoicism on belief definition of, 106; Stoicism on controlling
anger/rage, 104–9; Stoicism on detachment from, 87–88, 89–90, 91–93; transportation
through, 94–96
empathy: becoming another through sympathy,
94–96; development of, 50–51
Enchiridion (Epictetus),
85
Epictetus, 85, 87, 88, 89
Epicureanism, 88
“Ethical Choices: Individual Voices” (TV program),
24–25
ethics: Aristotle vs. Rousseau’s approach to,
25–30; military linking of good manners and, 100–105; Naval Academy course in, 86–87;
superseded by promotion of selfworth, 32; value-free approach to teaching, 25. See also morality
experience: character development and,
123–25; Discrimination Day school experiment, 124–25; POW survivor, 85–86;
teacher inclusion of moral, 3
extracurricular activities: experience generated
through, 121; as vital part of education, 115
Fallon Park Elementary School (Virginia), 38–39
Fekula, Michael J., 61
“felt knowledge,” 20–21
formalist tradition, 67–68
friendship bonds, 90–91
Gardner, Howard, 49
genetic influences, 54–55
ghetto education institutions, 179–80
Gilligan, Carol, 20
Golden Gate Elementary School (Oakland, Calif.),
8
Gould, David, 13–14
The Great Santini (film),
102
guilt development, 52
A Handbook For Developing
and Sustaining Honor Codes (Gould), 13
Harper’s magazine,
40
Harris, Eric, 35, 36
hidden curriculum practices, 152–53
Hierocles, 94, 96
higher education: academic integrity standards
programs in, 11–12; arguments against moral education in, 162–65; character
education in, 61–62; conclusions regarding civic/moral education in, 168–71;
corporate vs. public purpose model of, 149–52; debate over “whose” values to
use in, 155–62; hidden curriculum practices of, 152–53; intellectual weakness
of moral/civic, 167–68; moral/civic education programs of, 158–62; promoting
valueneutral, 152–55; significant influence on society by, 150–51; students’
frames of references and values assumptions of, 153–55; vocational training of,
165–66. See also schools
Hirsch, E. D., 10
Hoffman, Martin, 50
honor: Greek emphasis on education and, 15; moral
development theory on ideal of, 15–16; understood through historical context, 14n.17,
15
honor codes: benefits of, 16–17; core values transmitted
through, 12–17
honos (honor),
14–15
human nature: Christian doctrine on, 26, 28; Kant’s
dualistic view of, 68; Rousseau on, 29
identification-internationalization (psychoanalytic)
tradition, 67
Iliad (Homer),
90, 91
indoctrination: cases of educational, 17–18; criticism
of directive approach as, 34; debate over transmitting core values vs., 1–2
“Indoctrination versus Relativity in Value Education”
(Kohlberg), 2
induction parenting, 55–56
infant character development, 50–51, 118–19
institutions: case for authority in, 180–82; matching
moral/civic education approaches to, 168–69; moral neutrality and legitimacy of,
175–76; strategies of responsiveness used by, 176–80; success of ghetto
education, 179–80
internalization, 120
Israeli Youth Aliyah Kibbutz high school program,
133
Jarvis, William F. Washington, 39
Jefferson Junior High (Washington, D.C., ), 39
Jones, Ms. (teacher), 139–42
Josephson Institute of Ethics conference (1992),
37–38
Judeo-Christian tradition: directive style of
moral education and, 30; on healing of love compassion, 92; on human nature,
26, 28. See also religion
Just Community Schools: benefits of participation
in, 147–48; characterized by shared expectations/norms, 143–47; democratic
decision-making approach by, 129–30; democratic practices of, 134–38; democratic
role of teachers in, 138–43; effective approach taken by, 56, 57; schoolwide
cultural transformation stressed in, 46–47; weekly community meeting of, 134. See also Cluster
School
justice, 72–73
Kant, Immanuel, 67–68, 87, 103–4
Kerr, Clark, 176
kibbutz schools (Israel): Kohlberg’s report
on, 133; role of madrich (adult leader) in, 138–39
Kids with Character (Dallas), 41
King, Martin Luther, Jr., 124
Klebold, Dylan, 35, 36
Kochanska, Grazyna, 52
Kohlberg, Lawrence: cognitive moral development
approach, 31, 68–69, 164; democracy and community focus of, 143; on
effectiveness of Socratic questioning, 138; on importance of collective norms, 144,
145, 146; on indoctrination of children, 2; Just Community approach contributions
by, 129; on “little Republic” ideal school, 132–33, 148; on moral maturity of
justice, 72; teacher role in discipline studied by, 135
Kohn, Alfie, 2, 40
kosmopoliteˆs (cosmic,
universal citizen), 92–93
Lasley, Thomas, 40
Law of Fortuitous Reversals, 41
Law of Unintended Consequences, 41
Learn and Serve Higher Education initiative (Corporation
for National Service), 151
legitimate authority, 180–81
Leideker, M., 9
Leschner, Alan, 57
Lickona, Thomas, 48, 52
“little Republic” ideal school, 132–33, 148
Lord of the Flies (Golding),
29
Louis XVI, King (France), 176
MacIntyre, Alasdair, 4
madrich (kibbutz
school adult leader), 138–39, 141–42
Mann, Horace, 136
Marcus Aurelius, 88, 89, 94
Marquette University (Milwaukee), 62
Marx, Groucho, 176
maxims: defining, 6; passed during
adult-child interactions, 5–7, 21; Plato’s two, 69; significance of memorizing,
10; teaching strategies for learning, 9–10
McCabe, Donald, 11
McGuffey Readers, 30
Meditations (Marcus
Aurelius), 89
Meider, S., 6
Messiah College, 160
military man: camaraderie relationships to, 90–91;
emotional detachment of, 89–90; good manners/good morals of, 100–104; My Lai (Vietnam)
and, 107–9; Stoicism on anger and, 107–8; Stoicism emotional detachment and,
91–94; Stoicism sound bodies/minds belief and, 96–100; world citizenship notion
and, 93–94. See also Naval Academy; Stoicism philosophy
Mill, John Stuart, 33, 887
moral anatomy, 48–49
moral autonomy, 18–19
moral development theory: Aristotle vs. Rousseau
on, 25–30; cognitive, 31–33; competing perspectives of, 67–71; on ideal of
honor, 15–16; implications of, 173–75; Kohlberg’s model of, 68–69, 131–34, 164;
terms used to describe, 19–20
moral education: arguments against higher education,
162–65; Aristotelian approach to, 25–27, 35, 41; Augustinian doctrine regarding,
26, 28; college vocational training vs., 165–66; conclusions regarding higher
education, 168–71; directive style of, 30–31, 33; higher education approaches
to, 158–62; inspiring stories approach to, 33; intellectual weakness of higher
education, 167–68; Kohlberg’s interest in, 131–34; lessons of Stoicism for,
109–11; principles of, 114–15; progressive vs. traditional directive style of,
30; purpose of, 34; role of character values in, 121–23; Rousseau on, 27–30;
value-free approach to, 30–33; values, 44. See also character
education programs
The Moral Education of the
Child (Piaget), 137
Moral Education (Sizer
and Sizer lectures), 30
moral excellence conceptions, 72–77
moral exemplars: benefits of analyzing behavior
of, 77–80; impact on children by, 82
moral functioning: conception of moral excellence
and, 72–77; examining moral exemplars and their, 77–80; interactive nature of,
66–67; moral psychology applied to, 80–83; moral psychology’s preoccupation
with, 70–71; new focus on personality/character and, 71–80; tension between
agency and, 73, 82–83
moral identity: adult achievement of, 164; debate
over generational transmission of, 4; formation of, 53
morality: character as ability to behave, 48;
competing moral psychology perspectives of, 67–68; of constraint vs.
cooperation, 137; cultural differences in conceptions of, 157–58; implications
of “development” of, 173–75; Kohlberg’s model of, 68–69; military linking of
good manners and, 100–105; as part of everyday life, 81; working multifaceted
definition of, 66–67. See also ethics
“the morality of the classroom” discipline, 139–42
moral maturity: Kohlberg on early adult achievement
of, 164; Kohlberg’s cluster vision of, 72–74; virtues associated with, 74–75
moralogy, 44
moral personality: analysis of moral exemplars’s,
79–80; aspects of, 78; McAdams’s typology of personality assessment and, 79;
new focus of moral psychology on, 71–80
moral psychology: applications of, 80–83; competing
perspectives of, 67–71; emphasis on moral rationality by, 69–70; Kant’s formalist
tradition of, 67–68; Kohlberg’s structuralist cognitive-development tradition
of, 68–69, 131–34; on moral excellence conceptions, 72–77; new focus on
personality/character of, 71–80; social learning,
identification-internalization, cognitive-developmental traditions of, 67. See also Stoicism
philosophy
moral reasoning/rationality: competing perspectives
on, 67–71; development of, 53; emphasis of moral psychology on, 69–70; Kohlbert
on cultivation of, 131–34; opportunities to debate/reflect on, 60–61
moral schizophrenia, 70
moral values. See core
values
Mother Waddles, 170
My Lai (Vietnam), 107–9
National Institute on Drug Abuse, 57
Naval Academy: ethics course developed by, 86–87;
hierarchy of rank and respect at, 102–3; male/female body fat standards of, 99.
See also military man
Nero, 89
Nixon, Richard, 177
“The Nobel Prize for Being You” assignment, 32
Nucci, L., 48
obligations/rights link, 178
old Stoa, 88
“On Anger” (Seneca), 104
On Duties (Cicero),
89, 95, 102
On Ends (Cicero),
89
“On Favours” (Seneca), 101–2, 103
On Liberty (Mill),
33
parents: character development and, 55–56; involvement
in school’s character education by, 61, 116–17; role in character development
by, 53–54, 58–59; role of discipline stressed by, 119–21; role in education of
adult students by, 163
parochial ghetto schools, 179–80
Patroclus, 90, 91
peers: character development influence of, 54;
Just Community Schools use of discipline by, 143–47; madrich use of power
of, 139, 141–42; mentoring among, 115–16; morality of cooperation among, 137. See also students
person concept development, 50, 51
perspective-taking development, 52
Perzynski, Theodore, 125
Peters, Richard, 23
philia (friendship),
90–91
Piaget, Jean, 131, 133, 137, 138
Plato, 26, 69, 98–99
Pledge of Allegiance, 38, 40
Portland State University, 161
Positive Action, 57
POW survivor experience, 85–86
prevention behavior programs, 11
Prhalad, Anand, 7–8, 9
progressive moral education approach, 30, 34–35
proverb masters, 8
psychopathology, 51
rationalization, 75
Readings in Values
Clarification (Simon and Kirschenbaum), 31
religion: liberal humanism, 174–75;
responsibility to foster moral/civic learning
by, 165; teaching significance of historical, 116. See also Judeo-Christian
tradition
Republic (Plato),
98
Resolving Conflict Creatively Program, 46, 57,
58
Responsive Classroom, 46, 57
responsiveness strategies, 176–80
responsivity/nurturance parenting, 55
Rest, James, 154
Richard II (Shakespeare),
15
rights/obligations link, 178
Ring of Gyges (Platonic question), 15n.19
risk-prevention: current focus of character education
on, 11; research on drug risk factors and, 57–58
Roanoke antipoverty programs, 164, 170
Rolland, Susan, 125
Roman culture: Stoicism development in,
88–96; strong bodies/minds beliefs of, 98–99
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 25, 27–30, 35, 37, 41
Ryan, Kevin, 41
Saint Andrew’s High School (Boca Raton, Fla.),
13–14
Scheffler, Israel, 8–9
schools: apprenticeship model of, 137; authoritarian
vs. democratic participation, 135–36; character development influence of, 54;
character education programs and environment of, 130; Columbine High School
massacre (1999) impact on, 35–37, 39–40; community values/social roles reinforced
by, 116; current state of character education in, 45–47; deemphasized moral
functions perspective of, 19n.24; discipline methods for infractions by,
115–16; Discrimination Day experiment in Iowa classroom, 124–25; diversity
within unity approach by, 118; encouragement of self-discipline, internalization
by, 119–21; experience gained through, 123–25; good character expectations by,
60; influence of Rousseau’s thinking on, 30; integration between business world
and, 117; involvement of parents in character education by, 61; kibbutz, 133,
138–39; Kohlberg’s “little Republic,” 132–33, 148; “the morality of the
classroom” discipline in, 139–42; responsiveness strategies used by, 177–78; successful
character education approaches used by, 56–58; within communities, 116–17. See also character
education programs; higher education
Second Step, 57, 58
self: integrity and development of moral,
74–75; link between agency and sense of, 73–74; Stoicism on emotions and,
87–88, 89–90
self-control: ancient Greek/Roman thought on,
98; character development as acquiring, 118–19; danger of excessive, 119; development
of, 51–52
self-control/altruism modeled parenting
style, 56
self-discipline development, 120–21
Seneca, 88, 89, 101, 103, 104–5, 108
sex education, 116
shame: classical Greek society on, 14–15; as moral
emotion, 14; understood through historical context, 14n.17
Shay, Jonathan, 91
Shweder, Richard, 157
Sizer, Nancy, 30–31, 33, 59
Sizer, Theodore, 30–31, 33, 59
Skepticism, 88
Smith, Adam, 94–95
socialization: children and duty of, 23–24; Columbine
massacre (1999) and failure of, 35–37; maxims used during, 6
social-learning tradition, 67
social roles: school reinforcement of, 116;
of teachers in democratic schools, 135–38
society: duty to civilize children by, 23–24;
as existing in transmission of moral wisdom, 4; Law of Unintended Consequences
to, 41; maxims as “memory bank” of civilized, 6; pluralistic nature of
American, 156–57; role in character development by, 53–54; significant
influence of higher education on, 150–51; weakening morality of American,
113–14
Socrates, 98
Solomon, D., 57
Solzhenitsyn, Aleksandr, 10
stealing discipline (Cluster School), 144–47
Stockdale, James B., 85–86, 87
Stoicism philosophy: character development lessons
of, 109–11; on controlling anger/rage, 104–9; defining, 86; on detachment from
emotions, 87–88, 89–90, 91–93; on good manners, 101–2; historic development of,
88–96; incorporated in Naval Academy ethics course, 87; military man and,
91–94; on notion of world citizen, 92–94; regarding moderation, 100; sound
bodies/minds beliefs of, 96–100. See also military
man; moral psychology
structuralist cognitive-development
tradition, 68–69
student decision-making: Just Community Schools
use of, 129–30; Kohlberg’s recommended encouragement of, 132
students: academic values assumptions and frames
of references of, 153–55; adult status of higher education, 162–65; bonding between
teachers and, 125–27; core values transmitted through honor codes to, 12–17; culture
gap between teacher and, 142; defining moral autonomy of, 18–19; encouraging
community service by, 117; impact of school discipline methods on, 115–16; on
PBS program, 24–25; elfdiscipline development
by, 120–21; social environment influences on, 122–23; transmitting values vs.
indoctrination of, 2–3; vocational training of college, 165–66. See also peers
The Students Are Watching (Sizer
and Sizer), 59
sympathy, 94–96
Tappan, Mark, 3
Taylor, Charles, 21
Taylor-Thompson, Kim, 24
teachers: bonding between students and,
125–27; Columbine High School massacre reports by, 36; culture gap between
students and, 142; on family behavior, 59; inclusion of moral experience by, 3;
influence on child’s character by, 59–60; Just Community democratic role of,
138–43; new roles in democratic schools by, 135–38; role of discipline stressed
by, 119–21; socializer role of, 32n.18; strategies for teaching maxims by, 9–10
Teachers of My Youth (Scheffler),
8
Teresa, Mother, 10
Thompson, Hugh, 107–9
toddler character development, 50–51
United States Air Force Academy, 160–61
value-neutral education: as approach to ethics,
25; difficulty in maintaining higher, 152–55; used in sex, 116
values juggernaut, 40
values moral education approach, 44
values. See core
values
vocational training, 165–66
Volumnia, 90
Walker, Janet, 154
Waller, Willard, 142
Watson, M. S., 57
White, Vera, 39
Williamsburg Charter, 116
Youth Charter program, 40, 41
Zeno, 88
==============================