Anti-Americanism Report:
Anti-Americanism in Europe
Hoover Institution
Anti-Americanism
in Europe: A Cultural Problem (Hoover Institution 040300)
1. The
German Perception of the United States since September 11 and the European
Context
Representation
of the United States in German Print Media
Views of
a Changing World, June 2003
2. Not
Just a Friendly Disagreement: Anti-Americanism as Obsession
3.
Democratic War, Repressive Peace: On Really Existing Anti-Americanism
Anti-Americanism:
A European Ideology
Blissful
Ignorance and Anti-Americanism
5.
Anti-Americanism and the Movement against Globalization
Jean
Baudrillard and the Protest against Uniformity
Arundhati
Roy and the Fear of the Foreign
Theodor
Adorno: On the Inappropriateness of Anti-Americanism
==============================
By Russell A. Berman
http://www-hoover.stanford.edu/publications/books/antiamer.html
Our tarnished image in Europe: why has it become so pervasive?
Since September 11, 2001, the attitudes of Europeans toward the United States have grown increasingly more negative. For many in Europe, the terrorist attack on New York City was seen as evidence of how American behavior elicits hostility—and how it would be up to Americans to repent and change their ways. In this revealing look at the deep divide that has emerged, Russell A. Berman explores the various dimensions of contemporary European anti-Americanism.
The author shows how, as the process of post–cold war European unification has progressed, anti-Americanism has proven to be a useful ideology for the definition of a new European identity. He examines this emerging identity and shows how it has led Europeans to a position hostile to any "regime change" by the United States—no matter how bad the regime may be—whether in Serbia, Afghanistan, or Iraq.
Berman details the elements—some cultural, some simply irrational—of this disturbing movement and tells why it is likely to remain a feature of relations between the United States and Europe for the foreseeable future. He explains how anti-Americanism operates like an obsessive prejudice and stereotype, impervious to rational arguments or factual proof, and shows how the negative response to U.S. policies can be traced to a larger, more deeply rooted movement against globalization.
Anti-Americanism in Western Europe is not just a friendly disagreement, it is a widening chasm. This book makes a major contribution to understanding this important ideological challenge.
Russell A. Berman, the Walter A. Haas Professor in the Humanities at Stanford University, is a senior fellow, by courtesy, at the Hoover Institution.
==============================
As
the diplomatic relations between the United States and some of its traditional
European allies grew strained after September 11, so too did the attitudes of
Europeans regarding the United States decline considerably. Positive opinions
of the United States dropped in France from 62 percent in 1999/ 2000 to 43
percent in June 2003, as reported by the Pew Global Attitudes Project
(discussed in chapter 1). In Germany the fall was even more dramatic, from 78
percent to 45 percent, and in Spain, from 50 percent to 38 percent. One can
clearly conclude that large majorities in key Western European countries have
ceased to be positively predisposed to the United States.
Several
objective and strategic factors help explain this growth in anti-Americanism.
The collapse of the Soviet Union and the end of the cold war have meant that
Western Europe no longer needs the protection of U.S. troops, which in turn
makes a public anti-American rhetoric more permissible than in the past. In
addition, as the United States emerged as the single superpower (a tendency
long before 1989 but only explicit after the demise of the Soviet empire), it
became a more obvious target; Europeans could resent American power more while
also paradoxically expecting the United States to shoulder more international
responsibilities.
In
retrospect, the period between the fall of the Berlin wall on November 9, 1989,
and the terrorist attacks in Washington, D.C., and New York City on September
11, 2001, can be viewed as a transition period in the emergence of a new
international system, including a profound transformation of European attitudes
toward the United States. The United States responded to terrorism robustly
with the wars against the Taliban and against Saddam Hussein. Although a
minority of Europeans genuinely supported these wars, there was also extensive opposition,
based on an underlying inclination toward a policy of appeasement. This difference
heightened tensions across the Atlantic. For the United States, September 11
indicated the need for strategies to reduce security threats. For many
Europeans, September 11 was taken as evidence of how American behavior elicits
hostility and how it would therefore be up to Americans to repent and change
their ways. September 11 and its aftermath proved to be a turning point in
European anti-Americanism, which has become an increasingly open and acceptable
attitude. Yet this transformation of European attitudes regarding the United
States would not have been as pointed had it not been for another factor,
related to the strategic post–cold war changes. As the process of European
unification progressed, anti-Americanism proved to be a useful ideology for the
definition of a new European identity. Currently, the main way Europe defines
itself as European is precisely by underscoring its difference from the United
States. To be sure, this is not the only way to define Europe, nor must it
remain that way in the future. If the European political class were to speak
out more forcefully against anti-Americanism, other understandings of “Europe”
might be possible. Yet in the meantime, treating the United States as the
alternative to Europe—rather than as a partner— retains considerable
attraction.
Writing
in February 2002, after the success of the Afghanistan war, the author Salman
Rushdie commented: “Anybody who has visited Britain and Europe, or followed the
public conversation there during the past five months, will have been struck,
even shocked, by the depth of anti-American feeling among large segments of the
population, as well as the news media. Western anti-Americanism is an
altogether more petulant phenomenon than its Islamic counterpart and, oddly,
far more personalized. Muslim countries don’t like America’s power, its ‘arrogance,’
its success; in the non-American West, the main objection seems to be to
American people.”1 Anti-Americanism,
in other words, may take this or that policy dispute as a pretext for criticism
about the United States. European anti-Americanism, however, involves a
hostility that goes far beyond specific policies and entails a much larger and
generalized disdain for America and Americans. It has elements of ideology and
obsession; it is cultural and irrational; and it is likely to remain a feature of
relations between the United States and Europe for the foreseeable future.
Particularly in the cultural elite, but by no means only there, the animosity
toward the United States is deep. As celebrated German theater director Peter
Zadek has put it with admirable clarity: “I think that it is cowardly that many
people distinguish between the American people and the current American
administration. The Bush administration was more or less democratically
elected, and it had the support of the majority of Americans in its Iraq war.
One can therefore be against the Americans, just as most of the world was
against the Germans in the Second World War. In this sense, I am an anti-American.”2 This
one example stands for many instances of the European culture of
anti-Americanism.
This
book explores various dimensions of contemporary European anti-Americanism.
Because anti-Americanism is a cultural problem—albeit with enormous
consequences for policy— the tools of cultural analysis are necessary to
understand it. Chapter 1 examines several recent surveys in order to determine the
quantitative scope of anti-American sentiment, especially since September 11.
The focus is on Germany, the key continental European ally during the cold war
but also the site of the initial dispute over Iraq policy. German attitudes to
the United States are interesting in various ways: the positive image of the United
States has declined there more rapidly than in other European countries,
whereas on various cultural questions, the Germans (or the West Germans, at
least) are more like Americans than other Europeans. German anti-Americanism
has features that are peculiarly German, as well as epitomizing a larger European
phenomenon.
Because
anti-Americanism is so much a matter of culture, the subsequent chapters
examine various cultural traditions, intellectual historical lineages, and the
attitudes of members of the cultural elite. Chapter 2 describes how
anti-Americanism goes beyond rational debates over policy—a critic of this or
that American policy is hardly necessarily an anti-American—and takes on an
obsessive character. Anti-Americanism operates like a prejudice and a
stereotype in the sense that it is impervious to rational arguments or factual
proof. In general, European anti-Americanism has deep cultural roots,
stretching back for centuries. The discovery of a “new world” challenged the
European worldview and self-understanding, leading to various preconceptions about
America: too violent, too democratic, too powerful.
In
addition, this chapter suggests a typology of three different variants of
anti-Americanism: a predemocratic cultural elitism that dismisses American mass
culture; the antidemocratic legacy of the Communist attacks on the United
States, left over from the cold war; and a postdemocratic resentment that the United
States retains an independence and sovereignty while the European nations
submit increasingly to transnational forms of governance.
Chapter
3 examines the shape of anti-Americanism in the debates over the Iraq war. The
sudden rage that erupted against the United States in major Western European
cities, examined closely, is symptomatic of the emerging European identity. Although
critics of the war regularly warned against upheavals around the world, it was
primarily in Western Europe that anti-American demonstrators took to the
streets. By supporting a policy of appeasement toward Saddam Hussein and
opposing the democratization of Iraq, the Europeans, in the streets and in some
governments, shed light on the political substance at stake. Their reluctance
to criticize authoritarian regimes has led them to a position hostile to any
“regime change.” Indeed, for European anti-Americanism, no regime is so bad
that it could ever warrant supporting the United States in bringing that regime
to an end: not in Serbia, not in Afghanistan, and not in Iraq.
Chapter
4 explores the roots of anti-Americanism in this reluctance to criticize bad
regimes for fear of siding with the United States. The historical and
metaphorical frame around the two Iraq wars—the comparison of Saddam and
Hitler—turns out to be quite illuminating on this point. When all is said and done,
the world did not rush to oppose either dictator; on the contrary, appeasement
and a certain reality denial defined the relationship to Nazi Germany as much
as it did to Saddam’s Iraq. For Western Europeans, and perhaps for many others,
it has always been more comfortable to ignore the violence of totalitarian
states. Because the United States sets a higher moral standard in a way that
causes discomfort to the appeasers, it becomes the target of resentment:
another source of anti-Americanism.
The
fifth and final chapter looks at another variation of anti-Americanism: the
movement against globalization. Antiglobalization has become the most prominent
form of anticapitalism since the collapse of Communism. As post-Communist
anticapitalism, it overlaps considerably with anti-Americanism. This chapter
examines the rhetoric of anti-Americanism in the writings of the French
philosopher and social theorist Jean Baudrillard and the Indian author
Arundhati Roy; Roy’s anti-American writings have been widely circulated in
Western Europe in the context of the wars in Afghanistan and Iraq. Both writers
lodge the critique of the United States within frameworks of antiglobalization.
Their positions are contrasted with an alternative judgment from an earlier
historical period, that of the German philosopher Theodor Adorno, some of whose
writings on the legacy of Nazi Germany explore the overlap between anti-Americanism
and antimodernization. Adorno suggests that the greater orientation toward
democratic and free market structures in England and America explains their
historical willingness to confront totalitarianism, just as continental
European statism contributed to a predisposition to collaboration. This thesis
implies that contemporary Western European anti-Americanism is not just a
response to U.S. policies in Afghanistan and Iraq but a much deeper rejection
of those free market principles that Germans sometimes call “American
conditions.”
Anti-Americanism
is not going to disappear in Western Europe overnight. The debate that erupted
in the wake of September 11 has not been just a friendly disagreement. A deep divide
has emerged. This book is intended as a contribution to understanding this
important ideological challenge. San Francisco,
August 2003
1.
Salman Rushdie, “February 2002: Anti-Americanism,” in Rushdie, Step across This Line: Collected Nonfiction 1992–2002 (New
York: Random House, 2002), 343.
2.
“Kulturkampf? Ich bin dabei: Spiegelgespra¨ch,” Der Spiegel, July
14, 2003.
==============================
When
George W. Bush visited Berlin in May 2002, he attracted large and hostile
demonstrations. The recent war in Afghanistan had been very unpopular in
Germany and elsewhere in Western Europe, amplifying a diffuse anti-Americanism associated
with various policy decisions: the U.S. rejection of the Kyoto Treaty, the
opposition to the International Criminal Court, and other aspects of U.S.
foreign policy, especially support for Israel. Yet when Bush visited several
formerly Communist countries in Central and Eastern Europe during the
subsequent fall, his visit elicited friendly, pro-American crowds, especially
in Vilnius and Bucharest.
It
would be difficult to argue that American policies had changed in the interim
between the two visits in a way that could explain a shift in the foreign
perception of the United States. On the contrary, what is clearly at stake is
the phenomenon of how the United States is viewed differently in different countries.
In other words, the perception of the United States is not, or not only, a
function of the external factor of the character of American policy. Rather,
the perception of the United States in a particular country is very much framed
by internal factors, sets of local circumstances, cultural legacies, and
political habits. It is therefore plausible to surmise that the warm reception accorded
Bush in the formerly Communist capitals reflected the local memories of the
indispensable leadership role the United States had played in opposing Russian
domination during the cold war, leading up to the turning point of 1989. In
this chapter, however, the other side of the comparison is at stake: the internal
factors that determine the German perception of the United States, especially
the attitudes toward America since September 11. How have factors specific to
German culture and history influenced the perception of the United States? And
how does the German view of the United States fit into the larger European
context?
Before
proceeding to German public opinion data, however, it is important to consider
why Americans have become so pointedly concerned with foreign perceptions of
the United States. Various developments have contributed to a heightened attention
among Americans to their image abroad. The collapse of the Soviet Union and the
emergence of the United States as the sole superpower—a tendency under way long
before 1989 but only fully apparent afterward—imply a changed position of the
United States in the world and hence an interest in understanding the image of
the United States abroad. If it is the case that the single superpower cannot,
ultimately, avoid global responsibilities—otherwise it ceases to be a
superpower, after all—then it is in the rational interest of the superpower to understand
how it is viewed around the world.
In
addition to this pragmatic approach to the question of perception, one can
identify a cultural-critical approach as well: contemporary culture is often
defined by a so-called mass culture that tends to place greater weight on
questions of image, and therefore perception, than on matters of substance. It
follows that increasing concern is directed to the response to policy, how it
appears, or what “spin” it is given, rather than what the policy achieves
directly. This cultural problem is related to the extensive impact of the media
and the culture industry. A third context surrounding the interest in the
perception of the United States, of course, is a direct effect of September 11.
The
attacks on the World Trade Center and the Pentagon are widely understood as
attacks on the United States as a whole (i.e., on the American way of life)
symbolized by the two buildings. The growing curiosity about the perception of
the United States overseas represents an effort to explore the roots of this animosity
as a way to explain the terrorist attacks. Without discounting possible
benefits of this approach, it should be noted, of course, that this line of
thinking does tend to impute a legitimizing motivation to the September 11
attackers. Rather than seeing the terrorists as isolated extremists, driven by
idiosyncratic fanaticism, this approach implicitly links them to much larger
cultural perceptions. The policy consequence of this assumption is that, in
order to prevent further terrorist attacks, the United States should change its
image abroad by changing its ways—its policies and its “way of life”—rather
than by pursuing the suppression and eradication of specific terrorist networks.
This
policy implication indicates how deeply politicized the debate over perception
has become. It is useful to recall that there have been other periods during
which the United States faced considerable opposition or anti-Americanism
overseas, most notably in the context of the cold war in the 1950s and early
1960s. Yet despite the cliche´ of the ugly American, the foreign perception of
the United States did not expand into a major concern in domestic debates, for
several reasons. At that time, the United States was not the single superpower
but faced, on the contrary, the Soviet Union with its very real aspirations for
global power. This in turn implied that expressions of anti-Americanism could
be attributed, properly or not, to a realworld power conflict rather than to an
elusive matter of image management. Moreover, the American culture of the 1950s
and 1960s was certainly less image-obsessed than we are a half century later.
In addition, the United States had not suffered any blow to its sense of
security on the level of the September 11 attacks. Perhaps a comparison might
be drawn to the Soviet acquisition of the nuclear bomb; suddenly the American
sense of security associated with being the sole nuclear power disappeared. In
that cultural context, however, the political response was to ask about real
espionage: how they spy on us. In today’s image-obsessed culture, by way of
contrast, we are concerned with appearance: how they view us, and why they do
not like us.
One
further context explains the current interest in foreign perceptions of the
United States. Until the debates over the Vietnam War, an extensive bipartisan
foreign policy consensus prevailed. Anti-Americanism overseas could not be
transformed into political capital for domestic use. In contrast, today that foreign
policy consensus has broken down, in part due to the end of the cold war, the
single superpower status, and the lack of clear unanimity regarding an
appropriate strategy, evidenced in the debates over unilateralism and
multilateralism. United States politics in general have become more divisive,
ideological, and acrimonious. To some extent this changing character of domestic
political style can be explained by party realignments, to some extent by
deeper cultural changes. In any case, in the context of a missing foreign
policy consensus and an increasingly agonistic public debate, anti-Americanism
abroad, interpreted as opposition to specific American policies, gains much greater
resonance within American politics as part of the domestic partisan
competition, in a way, for example, that anti-American demonstrators in Europe
or Latin America in the 1950s could never achieve.
Because
anti-Americanism in the past could be attributed to Communist activism, it had
little partisan value in the centrist American political scene. With the
collapse of the Soviet Union, however, anti-Americanism could paradoxically
take on an appearance of legitimacy, to the extent that it could no longer be
dismissed as a Communist artifice and, on the contrary, could now be accepted
as a reasonable response to particular United States policies, especially when
those policies are themselves already contested in the increasingly partisan
domestic debates.
Therefore
the putative reasonableness and policy specificity of anti-Americanism become
key assumptions for domestic political debate. These assumptions are, however,
simultaneously subject to critical skepticism, in the sense that expressions of
sentiments hostile to the United States can be questioned: are they really
driven by U.S. policy or are there other motivations?
This
is precisely why questions regarding the origins of anti-Americanism are
raised: do negative images of the United States in general, or anti-American
demonstrations in particular, represent reasoned objections to U.S. government
actions (in the sense that changing a policy would establish goodwill), or are they
primarily expressions of local circumstances (which are likely to generate
hostility regardless of U.S. policy shifts)?
Should
hostile expressions in Germany be treated as cogent objections to misguided
policies emanating from Washington, or are they symptomatic of aspects of
German national history and, therefore, not directly pertinent to formulation
of policy in the United States (except perhaps to the extent that such policy refers
specifically to Germany)? To sort out answers to these questions, it becomes
necessary to inquire into the specific local circumstances in which particular
images of the United States develop. The contrast between the hostile
demonstrations in Berlin and the friendly demonstrations in Vilnius and
Bucharest is a case in point. In such cases, the image of the United States obviously
involves the acting out of local issues, rather than a considered deliberation
of particular policies.
Germany
is a rich and complex case with regard to the formulation of perspectives on
the United States. Few countries have had such intense and extended
interactions as have Germany and the United States. Germany and the United
States were opponents in the two world wars, and whereas West Germany drew
close to the United States, East Germany was a key member of the Soviet bloc,
with its own set of anti-American attitudes. In other words, the
twentieth-century legacy of German-American history involves considerable
grounds for negative predispositions. Although elsewhere in the formerly Communist
states of Eastern Europe, the anti-Communist foreign policy of the cold war
United States translates into pro-American sympathies today, a comparable
post-Communist bonus does not appear to apply in the new states of unified
Germany (i.e., the territories that formerly composed the German Democratic
Republic). Although the former East Germans are surely better off than the
populations of any of the other new democracies, they do not participate in the
same positive estimation of the United States. On the contrary, there is a
specifically German continuity from pre-1989 Communist anti-Americanism to
post-Communist anti-Americanism, which has been particularly relevant, given
the role of the former Communist Party—the Party of Democratic Socialism
(PDS)—and its ability to influence the larger German political landscape.
The
twentieth-century legacy of German-American relations therefore includes
grounds for suspicion but also a strong history of affection and idealization.
The post–Second World War experience of Americans by West Germans was crucial
and transformative. Although Americans were not genuinely welcomed as liberators
in 1945, the protection afforded by the United States against an expansionist
Soviet empire generated much affection among West Germans. From the Berlin
airlift of 1948 through the enormously resonant speech by President Kennedy in
West Berlin, with his assertion “Ich bin ein Berliner,” to President Reagan’s
call to “tear down” the Berlin wall, the relationship between the United States
and the Federal Republic of Germany grew strong and stable and with it so did connections
between American and West German society.
American
popular culture and American scholarship both had profound influence on postwar
German culture. Indeed, even the West German student movement of the 1960s,
which articulated deep criticisms of aspects of American foreign policy, was itself
formatively influenced by the character of the youth culture and the student
movement that had developed in the United States.
Thus
German perspectives on the United States developed against a background of a
mixture of negative and positive attitudes. Although these biases derive from
the twentieth-century historical experience of encounters with the United
States, they also build on much deeper cultural-historical stances: the
eighteenth-century German enlightenment idealization of the experiment of the
American republic and the nineteenth-century German romantic suspicion of
capitalism and democracy.1 Yet, for the matter at
hand—German perceptions of the United States after September 11—the specific
history of German attitudes to the United States is arguably less important
than German views of their own past. Contemporary, unified Germany maintains a
largely critical attitude to the militarism of its own national history and
tends to draw de facto pacifist lessons: war is regarded as the absolute evil,
military solutions to international problems are shunned at all costs, and
therefore any current war—such as the United States’ war in Afghanistan or Iraq—is
typically viewed through the lens of the German experience in the world wars.
This leads to the projection of German metaphors onto American policy: in the
extreme, George W. Bush is equated with Adolf Hitler (as in the grotesque
remark of the former German minister of justice Herta Da¨ubler-Gmelin).
Variants
of this equation are common (e.g., the suggestion that the attacks of September
11 were planned or facilitated by the Americans and were intended to play the
same role that the burning of the Reichstag did for the consolidation of Nazi power).
In these cases, the genuine psychic burden of the guilty German past is
presumably temporarily lifted through the accusation that the Americans of
today are, ultimately, no better than the Germans of the Nazi era. This is as
much a case of judging the present through the lens of the national past as is—with
alternative results—the East European, pro-American willingness to see current
U.S. policy in light of the U.S. foreign policy of the cold war era. The German
projection of its national history onto current events can even be taken one
step further: not only by identifying today’s Americans with Hitler-era Germans
but also by drawing a connection between the Anglo-American air war in the
Second World War and the bombing of Afghanistan and Iraq. Needless to say, the
equation entails a massive minimization of what took place during the Second
World War, and it ignores the precise targeting capabilities of new missile technologies.
The key point, however, is the remarkable degree to which Germans see current
events as repetitions of their own national past, even identifying with the
victim status of the targets of American foreign policy.
There
is one further dimension of the German situation that intrudes on current
perceptions of the United States: the process of European unification. An
aspiration to develop a unified continental political system has deep
historical roots. In its current form, it commenced after the Second World War
as a project for a common economic market in Western Europe. European
institutions have gradually grown more political (i.e., not solely economic) and
more regulatory. Some political powers of national governments have been
transferred to European institutions, including the maintenance of a currency:
the euro is now the coin of the realm through much of Europe, and monetary policy
has thereby ceased to be a national prerogative. In addition, Europe has
expanded its membership, largely due to the fall of the iron curtain and the
opportunity to integrate Central and Eastern European states. Although the
United States generally has supported the process of European unification, a
subtle shift has taken place, particularly since 1989. Although European unification
once represented part of the bulwark that the West presented against Soviet
expansionism, after the collapse of Russian hegemony the European Union began
to define itself in relation to the United States (i.e., as an alternative to
the United States in a hypothetically multipolar world). Anti-American
sentiment has become the vehicle for the expression of this new European
identity.
Meanwhile,
the European Union suffers from a so-called democracy deficit: political powers
have been shifted to a bureaucracy largely shielded from public scrutiny and
electoral control. This bureaucratization of Europe means that the process of
unification has little capacity to appeal to the ideals or loyalty of a
pan-European citizenry; so far, individuals in much of Europe typically remain
loyal to their respective nation-states rather than to the abstract superstate.
Germans, however, given their troubled national past, have been among the
strongest supporters of the European unification process: becoming more European
is a way to become less German. The central lesson on which this unification
process has been based involves the presumed urgency to overcome the egoism of
individual nations and replace it with multilateral cooperation. This
multilateralism entails a renunciation of elements of national sovereignty in
the name of greater cooperation among nation-states. Although many continental
European states are prepared to take this step, some are reluctant to do so
(especially the United Kingdom), and, in any case, the United States has shown
little interest in subjecting itself to international governance structures:
hence the debate over multilateralism and unilateralism that erupted in the
context of the Iraq war. This material frequently colors German views of the
United States. The United States and West Germany maintained a deep alliance
through the cold war decades, and unified Germany has inherited its role in
this partnership. However, unified Germany has also inherited another aspect of
the older West German political culture: a willingness to subordinate its
specific national interests to larger international, especially European,
processes. Because of its role in the two world wars, Germany today is
predisposed to renounce elements of its national sovereignty in order to become
a good European. Public opinion in Germany is therefore particularly suspicious
of the American reluctance to cede power to international governance
structures. In this case, it is not, strictly speaking, an internal German
factor that shapes the perception of the United States, but a regional process:
the relationship of Europe, of which Germany is a key component, to the United
States.
Several
surveys of representations of the United States and of public opinion regarding
foreign policy can help shed light on these matters. The study America’s Image Abroad,
conducted at Michigan State University, provides data concerning the
representation of the September 11 attacks and related issues during the autumn
of 2001.2 To be sure, one should be cautious not to overstate
the significance of these data. Although the study surveys several key organs
of the German print media, both daily newspapers and weekly news magazines, it
does not include electronic media, through which large sectors of the public receive
their news information. Moreover, the data are not corrected for circulation
size. References to the United States in newspapers with only local or regional
readership (e.g., Augsburger Allgemeine,
Su¨dwest Presse) are put on the same level as references in
the large-circulation de facto national newspapers (e.g., Frankfurter Allgemeine, Su¨ddeutsche Zeitung)
and in the influential weekly publications (Der Spiegel, Die Zeit). In order to extrapolate from
representations in the various press organs to public opinion in general, one
would have to factor in these various circulation profiles and their
implications for readership influence. Germany has a variegated media
environment, and it is not uncommon for readers, at least those in the educated
strata, to draw on combinations of these publications. At the other end of the
literacy spectrum, however, significant strata of the public only read the
mass-distribution boulevard press, such as Die Bildzeitung.
Although
the data collected cannot be directly mapped onto public opinion, they do at
least present an initial rough cut of the representation of the United States
under the impact of September 11 and as such provide some important insights
into German political culture. Particularly dramatic are the data collected regarding
the question, “How should America respond to the September 11 events?” The
aggregate findings display a profile polarized around diametrically opposed
positions, with 23 percent of the press comments attributed to the negative “Do
not use military tactics or force. Do not declare a war against terrorism or
those deemed responsible for it,” whereas 37.3 percent are counted for “Use
military force or bombings against the governments, states, or groups that
harbor or support those responsible for September 11. Make no compromises with
these governments.” The policy at stake, obviously, involved the pursuit of a
war against terrorism in the form of the campaign against the Taliban regime of
Afghanistan. German press representations appear, on first glance, to tilt
toward the promilitary and, in this historical context, pro-American option.
The
ratio of 37:23, however, is to some extent an arbitrary result of the structure
of the content analysis. If one takes into account the numerous other
responses, none of which on its own gets above 8 percent, and allocates them
reasonably between the two camps, the overall polarization becomes starker.
Thus one can attribute proposals to alleviate poverty, change foreign policy,
“pause and reflect soberly,” and work with the United Nations, to the antimilitary
camp. Alternatively, calls to improve intelligence, gather credible evidence,
work with the entire world, and attack (only) terrorist camps might be counted
on the military side of the ledger (arguably, some of these items belong to the
antimilitary camp, but that attribution would only amplify the results of this
exercise). Making these assumptions, one finds a split of 45.3 percent against
the use of force and 48.8 percent supporting it.
This
structural polarization is corroborated by an accompanying tendency. The data
display an increased polarization in October 2001, as measured against
September 2001. In other words, after the initial shock of September 11, and as
public debate unfolded, positions tended to harden into two opposing camps.
Thus (looking now only at the major categories and bracketing the smaller,
peripheral ones), expressions of opposition to American use of military force
rose from 18.6 percent of press comments in September 2001 to 30.1 percent in
October 2001 while support for military force grew from 26.3 percent to 46.9
percent. In fact, support grew to 75 percent in December 2001, although this
number is based on a much smaller evidence pool, and in any case, the
Afghanistan campaign had largely ended at this point. (It therefore made little
sense to oppose the use of force any longer, so that a reasonable comparison with
the data from previous months becomes difficult.) These data suggest a complex
representational process in the German print media. In the aftermath of September
11, it is clear that there was much support for American use of force as a
proper response, and not limited specifically to terrorist camps.
Nonetheless,
there is also evidence of dispute and polarization. The treatment of the issue
in the press was split nearly equally. Even in the context of the war against
the Taliban—where the case for a connection to September 11 was always much stronger
and clearer than it was later with the highly contested war policy in
Iraq—nearly half the press treatment opposed the unlimited military solution.
To be sure, there was evidence of a concurrent pro-American predisposition, and
the antiwar opposition represented a (slight) minority of items in the content analyses.
Still this minority indicated a nontrivial antiwar potential: precisely the
potential that turned into the crowds at the anti-Bush demonstrations in the
subsequent May and on which German Chancellor Gerhard Schroeder made his
electoral calculation a year later, when he chose to oppose the intervention in
Iraq.
The
findings for other aspects of the content analysis add interesting detail to
this hypothesis of a German press prepared to tilt toward the United States in
a post–September 11 solidarity effect but already displaying signs of
reluctance or even resistance. Thus with regard to the question of how Germany
should respond to September 11, a clear majority of 51.4 percent of the press
comments indicate support for working with the United States, even in military
responses. There is, curiously perhaps, more support for Germany to cooperate
with the United States, even in military steps, than there is for the United
States to pursue such military steps. One can surmise that for the German public
sphere, the need for identification with the United States was even stronger
than a judgment on the particular political means (i.e., some of the reluctance
to support military initiatives could be set aside in order to maintain loyalty
to the United States). This too points to a post–September 11 solidarity effect.
If
one also counts calls for cooperation with the United States in restricted
military responses (terrorist camps only) or nonmilitary responses, then the
hypothetically pro-American evidence count comes to 83.9 percent. However, it
is perhaps more reasonable to assume that these variants—restricted military
and nonmilitary responses—in the context of the German debate on the
Afghanistan war in effect represented positions defined as opposed to U.S.
government policy. If one combines these data (9.9 percent and 7.7 percent)
with a marginal call for an independent German strategy (0.6 percent) and other
opposition to support for the United States in general (1.1 percent), one
discovers a rejectionist field of a not insignificant 19.3 percent.
This,
it would seem, suggests that the notion of universal solidarity with the United
States in the immediate aftermath of September 11 is not tenable. From the very
start, there was a vocal minority position in precise and explicit opposition
to the policy pursued by the American government (i.e., the attack on the Taliban
regime in Afghanistan). It is fair to speculate that if nearly one-fifth of the
German press representation of the issue in the context of the Afghanistan War
(where the case was both clearest and temporally closest to the September 11
attacks) implied an adversarial attitude toward the United States, then it was
plausible to predict that a much greater hesitation would emerge regarding
American-led military solutions in the less obvious case of Iraq.
Other
aspects of German public culture are apparent in the data. The significance of
moderate centrist views is evident in the fact that 87.4 percent of the press
reports designate Osama bin Laden or Islamic fundamentalists as the
perpetrators of September 11. This is proof of the reasonable and democratic
predisposition of German public life. Nonetheless, the fringe position that
attributes the September 11 attacks to Israeli special forces is represented
minimally but noticeably, and equally on the Left (Die Tageszeitung) and the Right (Die Bildzeitung).
The convergence of left anti-Zionism and traditional right antisemitism is
certainly not a solely German phenomenon, but it takes place closer to the
center of public debate in Germany than it does elsewhere. Although these two
newspapers can be taken to represent the respective ends of the political
spectrum under discussion, they are surely not in any sense part of extremist subcultures.
The
data on understandings of the root causes of September 11 attribute 12.4
percent to religious fanaticism and 18.0 percent to Islamic fundamentalism,
making a total of 30.4 percent. Moreover this attribution increases from
September 2001 to October 2001, presumably an effect of the case against the
Taliban being made with increasing cogency. Nonetheless, in September 2001
nearly 30 percent of the references to the September 11 attacks blamed them on
U.S. policies, be it a matter of the support for Israel or the earlier support
for the Mujahideen against the Soviets in Afghanistan. In other words, the significant
support for the United States in the German public sphere was again accompanied
by varying degrees of reluctance, rejection, or opposition even immediately
after September 11.
Despite
the 58.0 percent describing September 11 as “an attack against freedom,
democracy, humanity, or the civilized world,” there is remarkable balance
between the assertions of a conflict of civilizations (10.2 percent) and
denials of this conflict (11.4 percent). That is to say, underneath a
presumably pro-American consensus, there is evidence of an unstable and
unsettled public opinion. In the same vein, one can contrast the strong 61.3
percent that attributes the U.S. motivation to a goal of stopping terrorism
(rather than some less-than-ideal ulterior motive) with the 43.5 percent that
negatively assess the American war in Afghanistan, describing U.S. humanitarian
aid as “useless, hypocritical or insincere.” In sum, the German press accounts
of America in the context of September 11 reflect a slight predisposition to
support the American initiative in the war against terrorism while also
revealing considerable hesitation just below the surface.
The
final pertinent data from this study involve descriptions of the United States.
Initially the findings seem unexciting: the only term that gets a significant
percentage of hits is the obvious designation of the United States as “the only
superpower” at 20.1 percent. Nearly all the many other terms get low ratings. Nonetheless,
explicitly negative characterizations total 13.4 percent, which is hardly
insignificant. These terms include designations such as indifferent, stupid,
exploitable, naı¨ve, moneyhungry, “capitalism in a negative sense,”
warlike, and terrorists.
These
data also corroborate the overall profile presented by the content analysis
data. The hypothesis of universal solidarity with the United States in the months
immediately following the September 11 attack is not borne out by the evidence.
Although German press representations of the United States in this period are
somewhat positive or pro-American, there are indications of instability in the
structure of public opinion and, depending on the particular question,
considerable hostility as well. This negative potential, recorded here in the
contents of the print media, could come to play a larger role during the
following eighteen months, as the German political leadership positioned itself
against the United States, and the United States proceeded from the war on
terrorism in Afghanistan to the less obvious and more consequential case of
regime change in Iraq.
The
textured account of the German press representations of the United States in
the fall of 2001 is corroborated in various ways by the findings of the public
opinion survey sponsored by the Chicago Council on Foreign Relations and the
German Marshall Fund in June of 2002.3 A
pro-American predisposition and sets of shared values coexist with hesitation,
opposition, and elements of anti-Americanism.
It
is certainly true that with regard to many issues, public opinion in Germany
and the United States is similar. This is hardly surprising: both countries are
advanced industrial societies with stable democratic regimes, similarities that
only amplify long histories of cultural interaction, from extensive German
emigration to the United States in the nineteenth century to the American occupation
in West Germany after the Second World War. Despite the hostile world-war
experiences themselves, extensive exchange and positive interaction have also
characterized the German-American relationship. Indeed, in the early 1990s it
seemed possible that Germany might even become the primary anchor of the
trans-Atlantic relationship, perhaps even displacing the special relationship
between the United States and the United Kingdom. Of course, against this not-so-distant
past of exceptionally strong German-American relations, the precipitous
deterioration of German-American relations since September 11 is all the more
remarkable.
The
proof of shared values in Germany and the United States—like the evidence of
extensive support for the United States in the German press after September
11—is pronounced. Seventy-three percent of Germans and 75 percent of Americans support
expanded education spending. Similarly, 67 percent of Germans support greater
programs to combat violence and crime, as compared with 70 percent of
Americans. In both cases, the differences are negligible; public values are
similar in the two countries. There is also considerable overlap in the
estimation of world problems. Fifty-five percent of Germans see Islamic
fundamentalism as a possible threat to their vital national interests, as
compared with 61 percent of Americans. Forty-seven percent of Germans view
global warming as extremely important, effectively identical with 46 percent of
Americans.
This
sort of evidence can be cited to show the continuing vitality of a community of
values, the shared perspectives in Germany and the United States, which can
then be taken as demonstrating the fundamentally solid relationship between the
two countries. Yet this reassuring conclusion would not only ignore the real
character of German-American relations between September 11 and the Iraq war.
It would also ignore the public opinion data that demonstrate the basis for
tension. As will be discussed later, there are plenty of policy points where
Germans and Americans do not see eye to eye. In other words, the political conflict
between Germany and the United States cannot be attributed only to diplomatic
failures or deleterious personal interactions between the respective political
leaders. Rather the Worldviews 2002
survey, examined closely, yields evidence of an anti-American potential
in German public opinion, which was foreshadowed in the content analysis of
German print media after September 11.
A
crucial issue involves attitudes toward future defense spending. In both
Germany and the United States 38 percent of those surveyed believe that defense
spending should not change, but that is as far as the similarity goes on this
point. Otherwise the data are diametrically opposed. In the United States, 44
percent support expanded defense spending, and 15 percent call for cutbacks; in
Germany, 45 percent urge cutbacks, and only 14 percent argue for expanding the
defense budget. The distinctiveness of the German position can be better
understood if it is compared with the aggregate European findings as well as
with those of other individual European countries. For Europe in general, there
is 22 percent support for expanded defense spending and 33 percent support for
less (i.e., Germans are not only less supportive of defense spending than are
Americans, but they are less supportive of defense spending than is Europe as a
whole). Only the Netherlands (6 percent) and Italy (12 percent) have lower
rates for supporting increased defense spending.
The
pronounced antimilitary sentiment in Germany is an effect of German national
history, the defeat in two world wars, the extraordinary devastation—physical
and moral—associated with the Second World War, and the habit acquired during
the cold war of relying on American military protection. That national history
structures public opinion on this point is confirmed by the findings for other
European countries. The German ratio for expanding and cutting back defense
spending, 14:45 (percentages of the polled public supporting expansion and
reduction), is closest to the Italian results of 12:52. (The results for the
Netherlands are anomalous because of a curiously high rate for making no change
and keeping defense spending at the same level.) In contrast, the two primary
American allies in the world wars display slight majorities for increased
spending: in the United Kingdom 24 percent for expanded spending and 21 percent
for cutbacks, and in France 28 percent for expansion and 23 percent for
cutbacks. Whether a country was on the winning or the losing side in the Second
World War evidently has a significant effect on attitudes toward defense spending.
The
findings for Poland are particularly noteworthy with percentages nearly
identical to the findings for the United States: 45 percent for expanded
spending and 14 percent for cutting back (indeed, if only by a 1 percent
difference, Polish public opinion supports increased defense spending more
adamantly than does American ). It is worthwhile to note that these findings
predate the “old Europe versus new Europe” controversy, but they lend
considerable credence to the hypothesis. The German public views defense
spending in the light of a catastrophic militaristic history; Polish public
opinion addresses the question in the light of a long history of threatened
independence and a need to be able to defend its territorial integrity and sovereignty.
When
asked to comment on whether the United States should exert strong leadership in
world affairs, the aggregate findings for Europe show 31 percent viewing such
an outcome as undesirable (22 percent as somewhat undesirable and 9 percent as
very undesirable). The German total is 27 percent (i.e., a somewhat less
negative view of American leadership than in Europe as a whole, although considerably
above the American response at 14 percent). The combined negative results for France
total 48 percent. With regard to hostility to American leadership in world
affairs, there is therefore a significant anti-American minority in Germany,
but it is less significant in scope than in Europe as a whole and considerably
smaller than in France.
German
attitudes to the United States, however, are not only the function of direct
estimations of U.S. policy, past or future. They are also consequences of how
Germans evaluate the European Union (EU) and their own role in world affairs.
Question 7 of the Worldviews 2002
survey asks whether it is desirable for the EU to exert strong
leadership. Twenty-seven percent of Germans saw a leadership role for the EU as
very desirable. Interestingly, this is the lowest rate for any European country
(except Poland, at 16 percent, which at that time was not in the EU).
Even
in the United States, more Americans saw a leadership role for the EU as
desirable (31 percent) than did Germans. The findings were 32 percent in the
United Kingdom, 40 percent in France, 42 percent in the Netherlands, and 53
percent in Italy. The Germans appear to be the least supportive of EU
leadership. Yet Question 9, asking whether one’s own country should play an
active role in world affairs, again found Germans least willing to be engaged.
Although it is true that a majority of 65 percent stated that Germany should be
active in world matters, that rate is far below the aggregate European findings
of 78 percent and positively overshadowed by 82 percent in the United Kingdom, 86
percent in France, and even 90 percent in Italy. In both cases, the German
findings indicate a greater hesitation, on the European and the national level,
to take on prominent responsibilities in world affairs. It is plausible to
argue that, as with defense spending, the German national past restrains the
German public from articulating an aspiration for leadership in international matters.
This
result is confirmed by another German anomaly. Sixty-five percent of Europeans
support the notion that the EU should become a superpower like the United
States. In Italy the rate soars to 76 percent and in France to 91percent. The
finding for Germany is a humble 48 percent, the only finding below 50 percent
for any European country. As in the above examples, Germans display a cautious
predisposition to avoid exposure in world affairs. Yet among those Europeans
who do support superpower status for the EU, there is considerable variation in
their vision for a future relationship with the United States.
Although
most respondents in all countries favor cooperation with the United States over
competition, the findings for Germany indicate a significantly more
competitive, and therefore less cooperative, relationship with the United
States than is expressed by the public elsewhere in Europe. Eleven percent of Europeans
favor a competitive relationship with the United States: the figure for Germany
is 22 percent, as compared with France at 9 percent, the United Kingdom at 7
percent, and Italy at 5 percent. Meanwhile cooperation is favored by 84 percent
of Europeans in general, 87 percent of the French, 89 percent of the British,
92 percent of the Italians, but only 70 percent of the Germans. Clearly, even
in Germany, the proponents of cooperation are more numerous than are the
proponents of competition. Nonetheless, Germany tilts toward a more adversarial
posture to the United States in a way that distinguishes it from its European
neighbors. This finding confirms the observation in the print media content
analyses of a significant minority predisposition toward anti-American
positions.
Still,
the data leave us with a seemingly paradoxical finding: a German public opinion
that, in response to several questions, displayed a greater hesitation toward
world affairs than was characteristic of other European nations, yet at the
same time evidence of a possibly greater adversarial stance toward the United
States than displayed elsewhere in Europe. Both attitudes can, of course, be
explained by the internal factors of German national history: the scars of
earlier German international ambitions on the one hand, and on the other,
resentment against the United States, the erstwhile opponent. This profile also
maps onto the cultural-historical model of a romantic “German interiority”: an
inward-turning rejection of the world, coupled with an imperious external
projection. As tempting as the thesis might be, however, the data at hand are
insufficient to prove it. The two positions at stake—international hesitation
and competition with the United States—are not conclusively linked (i.e., the findings may well derive from
separate sectors of the public). One can conjecture, for example, that the
greater reluctance to engage in international matters, reflecting the German past,
might be associated with older generations, and the adversarial relationship to
the United States might plausibly derive from the ideological background of the
population in the new states (i.e. the formerly Communist East Germany). More
differentiated data would be needed to explore these hypotheses.
While
a “German interiority” hypothesis is not conclusively supported by the data,
nothing disproves it either. Greater demographic differentiation of the data
would be helpful, for example, in order to distinguish among the attitudes of
various population sectors. Nonetheless certain conclusions are possible. The
content analysis identified a preponderance of pro-American descriptors in the
immediate aftermath of September 11; part of that support may represent a
September 11 solidarity effect, but surely some indicates older pro-American
sympathies in parts of the German public. Yet any solidarity effect related to
the September 11 attacks was, as we have seen, clearly not universal.
Therefore, it appears that the later deterioration of German-American relations
cannot be attributed to some failure to make the American case in the German
press. On the contrary, that case was being made from September 2001 on. The point
is rather that support for the United States was never universal; other
political positions were also present in the public debate, and this debate
reflected deep fissures in German attitudes regarding world affairs. In other
words, internal factors— German history, cultural values, and the structure of
public debate—have evidently played crucial roles in formulating German
attitudes toward the United States, including anti-American sentiments.
The
Pew Global Attitudes Project survey, Views of a Changing World, June 2003,
provides insights that allow us to trace the problem of Germany and the United
States out another year. The image of the United States throughout Europe
dipped in the course of the Afghanistan and Iraq wars, but by June of 2003 it
rebounded, although not to the levels of 1999/2000. Nowhere has this trajectory
been as precipitous as in Germany: from a 78 percent favorable image of the
United States in 1999/2000 to 61 percent in the summer of 2002 (Schroeder election
campaign) to 25 percent in March of 2003 (Iraq war) and then to 45 percent in
June 2003. The difference between the extensive support for the United States
at the outset to the June 2003 standing of 45 percent—in other words, less than
half of Germans having a positive image of the United States— is a measure of
the dramatic decline in German-American relations. These data also shed light
on the question of the internalexternal formulation of attitudes toward the
United States. The fact that similarly curved trajectories are observable in
other European countries indicates that any adequate explanation cannot be
restricted to endogenous German circumstances alone.
External
factors are clearly at stake (i.e., the character of United States policy and
the European, rather than merely German, perspective). Yet the fact that the
German curve is so extreme is a result of internal German cultural factors: the
pro-American legacy of cold war era relations on the one hand, and on the
other, the devastating judgment on the American wars viewed through the
historically over-determined lens of German pacifism. The positive approval
rate for the United States in Germany has dropped by a remarkable 33 percentage
points, more than it has dropped anywhere else. (The rate in France has gone
from 62 percent to 43 percent, a loss of only 19 points; in Italy, from 76 percent
to 60 percent, a loss of 16 points; and in Russia, from 37 percent to 36
percent, a loss of just 1 point.)4
It
is not unreasonable to assume that estimations of another country are based
partly on perceptions of value systems: shared values may support a positive
estimation, whereas conflicting values may lead to negative judgments. In this
case, it is worthwhile to differentiate among various constellations: German congruence
with American values because of a shared “western” paradigm; differences
between America and Europe, including Germany; differences within Europe; and
so forth. The Pew study provides examples of some of the possible permutations.
Evaluating the statement “Most people are better off in a free market economy,
even though some people are rich and some are poor,” 72 percent of Americans
said they would completely agree or mostly agree. The finding for Germany is 69
percent, although in West Germany the finding is identical with that of the
United States, at 72 percent. Findings in other Western European countries vary
minimally: United Kingdom, 66 percent; France, 61 percent; Italy, 71 percent.
Interestingly, the free market finds considerably less approval in Eastern
Europe: Poland at 44 percent; Russia at 45 percent; and Bulgaria at 31 percent.
(The most westernized part of Eastern Europe, the Czech Republic, however,
shows 62 percent support for the free market, higher than in France.) In
general, then, Western Europe appears closer to the United States on the
question of the free market than does Eastern Europe, and Germany is the country
most like the United States.5
Yet
when the statement is replaced with one regarding individual freedom and the
force of social conditions, the findings change significantly. Evaluating the
statement “Success in life is pretty much determined by forces outside our
control,” 32 percent of Americans completely or mostly agreed. The German finding
is quite different, with 68 percent asserting the power of uncontrollable
social forces (i.e., the opposite of individual initiative). This finding is at
the high end of comparable Western European findings: the United Kingdom at 58
percent, France at 54 percent, Italy at 66 percent. Several of the Eastern European
findings are surprisingly lower than those from Western Europe, that is, closer
to the American data, although still much higher: Bulgaria at 52 percent, the
Czech Republic at 47 percent, the Slovak Republic at 49 percent, but Poland at
63 percent (higher than many Western European countries but still lower than
Germany). To the extent that, in the aggregate, the Eastern European findings
are closer to the American, one finds a corroboration of an aspect of the “new
Europe” thesis: the formerly Communist countries discovering an affinity with
the United States that divides them, even in values orientation, from parts of
Western Europe.6 In any case, Germany is least like the United
States on this point: where Americans trust individual initiative, Germans look
to the power of larger social forces.
One
final variant on the same subject matter shuffles the deck again. Asked to
choose between two desiderata, 58 percent of Americans chose to be “free to
pursue goals without interference from the state” as opposed to 34 percent who
opted for a “state guarantee that nobody is in need.” No other advanced
industrial country displays as stark a profile. Comparing only the “state guarantee,”
which received 34 percent in the United States, the United Kingdom measures 62
percent, France 62 percent, Italy 71 percent, and Germany 57 percent.7 If
one looks only at West Germany (in other words, if one excludes the post-Communist
effect from East Germany), the finding is lower, at 52 percent. Interestingly,
the Germans are in a liminal position: very much within the European range on
this question, with a preference for state intervention, but at the American, more
individualistic, end of the spectrum. Arguably, the severe decline of the
positive American image in Germany is a result of this particular values
structure: Germans are, in some ways, most like Americans, at least within the
Western European group, and therefore they are most susceptible not only to
identification but also to disappointment. Although they are the Europeans
closest to the American apprehension regarding an intrusive state, they are
also furthest from Americans in their deterministic estimation of the power of
social conditions over individual initiative.
Skepticism
of a strong state (presumably a legacy of the Nazi experience) coexists,
counterintuitively, with much less of an individualistic ethos. The combination
suggests a characteristically German orientation toward conservative stability,
implying potential discomfort with the dynamic changes sometimes associated
with the United States and American society.
The
various data suggest a complex German perception of the United States,
resulting from a long and intricate history. As soon as one concedes that
different nations may respond to the United States differently, one has to
recognize the role of local cultures and therefore of internal factors. It is
hardly surprising that fragments of the long German-American history resurface to
shape the cultural context within which contemporary American policy and
actions are judged.
The
complexity of German-American relations explains the fragmented findings in the
print media data survey: the strong clustering of support for and opposition to
U.S. initiatives. This bipolarity explains a curious aspect of the debate about
German attitudes to the United States: assertions of anti-Americanism typically
elicit denials and demonstrations of extensive appreciation for the United
States. The distinctiveness of the German case is that anti-Americanism and
philo-Americanism exist side by side. As much as Germany as a whole shares many
American values, it could also nurture the antiwestern and anti-American subculture
where the September 11 conspiracy germinated.
The
data unfortunately lack the demographic precision that would allow more
specific attribution of anti-American attitudes (e.g., on the basis of age,
gender, income, education, or region). Nonetheless, the negative
characterizations in the print media and some of the value conflicts allow a
tentative inventory of the types of anti-Americanism. The association of
Americans with “capitalism in a negative sense” in the context of the
hesitations regarding individualism indicates that an older, culturally
conservative set of anxieties regarding the dynamism of capitalism and
democracy may be lingering as part of Germany’s cultural heritage. This
predemocratic anti-Americanism finds expression in contempt for aspects of
American mass culture. In contrast, there is surely a separate Communist
anti-Americanism, inherited from the ideological inculcations of East Germany:
hence the attacks on American imperialism and the predisposition to denounce
the wars in Afghanistan and Iraq simply as continuities of the U.S. history of
interventions in the third world during the cold war: Iraq as Vietnam, and so
forth. Finally, a postdemocratic anti-Americanism has emerged (i.e., an
anti-Americanism driven by the resentment that the United States has been unwilling
to cede sovereignty to the structures of international governance, as European
states have done in the process of European unification). This difference has
grown into an enormous conflict between the United States and the European Union.
Considerable hostility to the United States is in fact fueled by the tenacity
with which the American government has resisted such internationalization and
insisted on the priority of national democratic processes. That this
“unilateralism” is so irksome to Germany only reflects the passion with which
German politicians have been eager to pursue a postnational form of government.
To the extent, however, that democratic legitimation still takes place largely
on national (if not regional and local) levels, resentment develops in response
to this loss of sovereignty. American resistance to this tendency fans the
flames all the more. Whether, and in what ways, these three hypothetical models
map onto aspects of public opinion remains to be studied. How they inform the
ideological life of anti-Americanism is discussed in the next chapter.
1.
Cf. Dan Diner, America in the Eyes of the
Germans: An Essay on Anti-Americanism, trans.
Allison Brown (Princeton: Markus Wiener, 1996).
2.
Vladimir Shlapentokh and Joshua Woods, America’s Image
Abroad (forthcoming).
3.
Chicago Council on Foreign Relations, Worldviews
2002: Comparing American and European Public Opinion on Foreign Policy (Chicago
Council on Foreign Relations,
2002). http://www.worldviews.org.
4.
Pew Global Attitudes Project, Views of a
Changing World, June 2003 (Washington, D.C.: Pew Research Center for
the People and the Press), 19.
5.
Ibid., T-6.
6.
Ibid., T-7.
7.
Ibid., T-42.
==============================
For a
brief moment after the fall of the Berlin wall, anti-Americanism seemed to have
disappeared, especially in Germany, where decades of American foreign
policy—the airlift, Kennedy in Berlin, Reagan’s call to tear down the
wall—culminated in a clear victory. In fact, that triumph cast a glow far beyond
Germany as well. The Soviet Union, the overriding opponent in one of the
defining conflicts of the last century, had been defeated. America and the
values of liberal democracy and neoliberal capitalism were the undisputed
winners. The Left, the traditional locus of most anti-Americanism, was in
disarray. The only remaining opponents were on the far Right, isolated European
ideologues of anti-American anticapitalism.
Yet
the moment was brief, ending quickly with the onset of the 1991 Gulf war, which
elicited a widespread peace movement, notably in Germany, which treated the
American-led international coalition against Iraq as an expression of a
malicious imperialist design, rather than as a response to the Iraqi occupation
of Kuwait.1 Although it was indeed a new historical epoch—the
cold war had ended, and with it the Soviet inspiration for anti-American
propaganda—an anti-American political subculture continued to flourish. In
fact, that hostility grew throughout the course of the decade, providing the
defining framework for European debates around an ever-shifting set of topical
concerns: the Israeli-Palestinian conflict, the anxieties regarding
globalization, international economic relations, and the efforts to develop an
international agenda for ecological concerns, which came to be associated with
the negotiations in Kyoto. No matter how the specific topic migrated, a
discursive framework remained constant, always casting America as the fundamental
source of discord. This analytic predisposition was nowhere more common than in
Germany. While the terrorist attacks of September 11, 2001, produced a
momentary solidarity effect with the United States, they did not significantly
mitigate the anti-Americanism that grew widespread in the Western European
public.
In
fact, it was precisely that vigorous anti-American subculture that made Germany
such a hospitable venue for Mohammed Atta and his terrorist partners as they
prepared for the attacks on Washington, D.C., and New York. Yet, far from
recognizing the European responsibility for having nurtured, harbored, and
funded terrorists and terrorist networks, anti-Americans turn matters on their
head, grotesquely blaming the United States for 9/11. For anti-Americans,
especially in Europe, the United States is always guilty, even when it is the victim.
Logic ceases to matter, allowing for mutually exclusive accusations. For
example, while some anti-Americans suggest that terrorists carried out 9/11 in
response to the alleged provocations of American foreign policy (suggesting
that the attacks were a necessary consequence of U.S. policy), others insinuate
that it was the Americans themselves who had engaged in a secret plot to attack
the Pentagon and the World Trade Center in order to gain political advantage by
acting as agents provocateurs. This conspiracy theory proposition is of course
outrageous, but—like most extremist propositions—it is ultimately undisprovable
to those who enjoy indulging in such fantasies and who are always willing to
believe the worst and most macabre claims about the U.S. government. However,
the former position, interpreting the attacks as a plausible response to American
foreign policy, is equally obnoxious because it is intended as an implicit
justification for terror. As will be discussed later, there may well be a
relationship between the attacks—standing now as the supreme expression of
anti-Americanism— and aspects of U.S. policy, but in a very different sense from
the anti-American claim that U.S. policy is the ultimate cause. For now,
however, suffice it to say that anti-Americanism has become an important factor
in contemporary political life, in Germany and elsewhere in Europe—despite the
end of Communism and despite the scope of the terrorist threat. Hence the urgency
of posing the question: Where does anti-Americanism come from?
It
is a frequent misunderstanding to treat the term “anti-Americanism” as a
designation for any opposition to a particular policy of the U.S. government or
to the influence of American society and culture. If that broad definition were
to apply, then reasonable critics of policy matters or cultural influence would
fit the bill. Such an expansive definition renders the term useless. Not every
opponent of American tax policy, for example, or every critic of American films
is necessarily “anti-American.” Anti-Americanism has nothing to do with
friendly disputes or reasonable disagreements. Instead, as French author Jean-Franc¸ois
Revel has put it, it is an “obsession.”2 Anti-Americanism
is indicated precisely when reasoned argument gives way to sweeping
generalizations and hostile innuendo, and the obsessive thought structures of
prejudice and stereotype prevail.
Although
a particular policy dispute may serve as a pretext, anti-Americanism is driven
by a deeper and more expansive fixation on an image or idea of America,
burdened with multiple negative associations that extend far beyond a bone of
contention about any particular policy.
If a
European dislikes jazz, that does not make him anti-American. It is only a
matter of musical taste. However, if the dislike is embedded in a racist
dismissal of African-Americans, then it does become a matter of
anti-Americanism: prejudicial obsession has displaced a possible musical
discussion. Similar distinctions apply in foreign policy matters. Criticism of
American policy in Iraq is, in and of itself, not anti-American, but when—as
was the case in Germany—that criticism is accompanied by a general dismissal of
“American conditions,” one has to recognize that anti-Americanism has come into
play. A useful test is refutability: in a policy debate on Iraq, one can
imagine attempting to rebut critics who present a specific rationale, but it is
impossible to mount a meaningfully argued reply to irrational prejudice.
Anti-Americanism
functions like a prejudice, magnifying the power and presence of its presumed
opponent, turning it into a ubiquitous threat. The empirical superiority of American
military power, for example, is transformed by the anti-American imagination
into a fantasy of infinite omnipotence: there is no evil in the world that
cannot be blamed on American action, if only because the one superpower did not
choose to stop it. Why should American humanitarian motives be believed in any
single case if Americans have failed to pursue them in all possible cases?
Because America is assumed to have unlimited power, it can be given unlimited
blame. Any event in the world can therefore be attributed to the machinations
of American conspiracy.
This
structure of thinking is comparable to other political fantasies. At the height
of the cold war, the core supporters of Joseph McCarthy interpreted all the
events around them in terms of an allegedly perfectly functioning Communist
conspiracy. Antisemites, similarly, have always been able to imagine an ineluctable
network of Jewish power. As a paranoid fantasy, anti-Americanism is cut from
the same cloth. Instead of facing up to the detailed complexity of reality, it
can only see Washington’s hand controlling every conflict. The point is not
that the United States is weak—on the contrary, it is indisputably the one
superpower—but the United States is not, indeed can never be, as infinitely strong
as the anti-American true believer imagines. This disjunction between American
reality and the anti-American fantasy is symptomatic. The character of
prejudice is such that it ultimately has very little to do with the reality of
its object. Yet while the discourse of anti-Americanism has little to do with
American reality, it does reveal the character and mentality of anti-American
Europe.
This
leads to the central claim in this chapter: anti-Americanism is not a response
to American policies, American influence, or any broader process of
“Americanization.” The anti-American may of course point to an allegedly
ubiquitous American presence in order to legitimate a hostile response: because
American power is allegedly unlimited, America must be opposed everywhere. Yet
this insinuated causality is ultimately not plausible. Anti-Americanism has a
secret life of its own. It cannot be correlated to specific instances of
American presence: hence the proposition that anti-Americanism is largely
independent of American policy or presence (or Americanization). Anti-Americanism
is not a rational response to American action; rather, the fantasy of infinite
American presence is a product of the anti-American’s heated imagination.
The
assertion that anti-Americanism is not the effect for which American action was
the cause can be demonstrated in several ways. Although anti-Americanism is
surely only a minority position in all national populations, one can find
evidence of anti-Americanism in many different settings: in countries with histories
of a considerable American presence (like Germany) as well as in countries with
very different histories of involvement with the United States (like France).
Yet since a comparable (if not fully identical) anti-Americanism colors
political culture in those two countries, then clearly the history of
occupation and Americanization in Germany—a history that France does not share—is
not a pertinent variable. Western European anti-Americanism takes place in
countries with very different degrees of Americanization and therefore very
different experiences of American reality. The fact that anti-Americanism can
appear in countries whose encounters with the United States have been radically
different from each other shows that anti-Americanism is not the function of a
real-world experience of the United States or of American behavior. Far from a
reasonable response to real-world situations, it is a political fantasy, an
irrational, ideological view of the world that spreads largely independently of
any objective contact with the United States or its culture.
With
regard to Germany, the key country in the process of European unification,
three further observations bolster the claim that anti-Americanism is not
explicable as an effect of American action. First, to the extent that American
policy serves as a pretext for anti-Americanism, a curiously selective vision applies.
Currently, at least, German anti-Americanism refers to American foreign policy,
particularly in Iraq, but then it is surely odd that the elements of American
foreign policy most relevant to Germany—such as the support for German
unification, against the implicit resistance of France and England—have dropped
out of the discussion.3 If anti-Americanism were
genuinely a response to American policies, then one would expect that American
policy toward Germany would also figure in the German discussion, and not
merely American policy toward Iraq. Of course, one can assume that an
underlying resentment of German unification and nostalgia for the Communist
regime of East Germany may fuel some of the anti-Americanism, at least in the
circles of the former Communist Party (the PDS). In this case, the paradox of
German anti-Americanism would be no paradox at all but merely a lingering effect
of the cold war. Yet although there is surely an element of this Communist
effect in the post-Communist world, it is only part of the larger phenomenon, which
requires a more comprehensive account: German anti-Americanism includes a
Communist element but clearly extends far beyond the Communist camp and cannot
be adequately explained as a desire to resurrect the East German regime. In any
case, the fact that it is American foreign policy that is under attack, whereas
American foreign policy in relation to Germany is excluded from the discussion,
demonstrates that anti-Americanism does not represent a rational response to
policy. On the contrary, it is about fantasy and ideology: anti-Americanism,
while taking the United States as a pretext, in fact expresses some other
displaced anger. It is evidently not American actions that elicit the hostile
sentiment.
Second,
the lack of a causal connection between American presence and anti-Americanism
is evidenced in Germany insofar as anti-Americanism has increased precisely as
the American military presence in Germany has decreased, in the wake of
unification. The willingness of leading German public figures to engage in
hostile characterizations of the United States is greater, even though there
are fewer Americans around and there is presumably less American influence.
When American troops were at full strength, no German Chancellor would have campaigned
with anti-American rhetoric, and no German minister would have compared an
American president to Hitler. It is hard to avoid the speculation that a
certain German nationalist rhetoric only became possible once American troop
size declined. Now that American troops are no longer necessary to face down
the Soviet military in Central Europe, there is less reason to refrain from
making political capital out of anti-American rhetoric.
Yet
it is not even necessary to make the strong case: greater anti-Americanism in
the context of less American presence. To show the lack of a causal
relationship between American action and anti-American sentiment, it is
sufficient to point out that the enormous reduction of American troop size has
simply not led to a corollary reduction in anti-Americanism. For example,
during the “peace movement” of the 1980s involving the NATO double-track
decision and the stationing of the Pershing missiles, much to-do was made of
presumed restrictions imposed on West German sovereignty because of the postwar
power relations and the dependence on the United States. A certain hostility to
America followed, or was imagined to follow, from that situation; it was argued
that the post-1945 limitation on West German sovereignty imposed by the
victorious United States was grounds for anti-American feeling. With the
unification of Germany, that restriction on German sovereignty disappeared; nonetheless,
a similar hostility continues to be directed at the United States. Thus the
claim made during the 1980s that anti-Americanism was due to the perceived
restriction of German sovereignty by American power on the basis of post–Second
World War arrangements is obviously not tenable. Even though Germany regained
its full sovereignty and the alleged grounds for anti-American sentiment
disappeared, anti-Americanism continued to thrive. This is further evidence
that German anti-Americanism has nothing to do with these aspects of German-American
relations. Indeed anti-Americanism appears to be independent of the real
character of these relations altogether. It is this lack of connection to
reality that makes it a matter of ideology. Yet ideologies and fantasies can
have very real impact on the substance of politics.
It
is, however, a third observation that clinches the argument, demonstrating the
independence of anti-Americanism from American actions. Not only is anti-Americanism
found in contexts where no significant Americanization (or occupation) has
taken place; not only does anti-Americanism evidently postdate the decline of
an American presence in Germany; but in fact, anti-Americanism long predates
the post–Second World War occupation and anything that might properly be
described as Americanization. Anti-Americanism is not a response to particular actions
or deeds but a cultural mentality that, emerging long before the rise of
American power in the early twentieth century, is a reaction against the very
presence of America in the world. The European discovery of the new world upset
the traditional European worldview, with Europe self-confidently at the center.
Indeed, ever since the so-called first contact of European travelers with the
inhabitants of the new world, Europeans have expressed anxieties regarding the
brute nature, the presumed absence of history, and an undifferentiated
homogeneity imputed to the western hemisphere.4 These
are precisely the standard tropes of anti-Americanism, an ideology with a long past,
replete with stereotypes that are regularly recycled in new historical
circumstances.
A
German discourse of anti-Americanism became prominent, at the latest, in the
early nineteenth century as romantic authors like the poet Nikolaus Lenau
increasingly described the United States in pejorative terms, associated with
their negative judgments on both its capitalism and its democracy. In contrast,
the towering German author of the age, Johann Wolfgang Goethe, repeatedly
expressed admiration for the young American republic. His opposition to the
romantic antimodern reaction indicates the initial phase of a positive German
attraction to America and the values of modernity associated with the American Revolution.5 The
deep, competing currents of pro-American and anti-American perspectives in
German culture, in other words, are quite old, which underscores why German anti-Americanism
cannot be explained away as a friendly policy dispute or even as a response to
aspects of the role the United States has played in Germany in the twentieth
century. The terms of the anti-American discourse have been in circulation at
least since the romantic early nineteenth century. Thus, it is not anything that
the United States does to Germany, no recognizable Americanization, that
elicits anti-Americanism. It is rather the mere fact of the presence, in the
world, of a society defined in terms of capitalism and democracy that
scandalizes sectors of German and old European society. It is not an intrusive
imposition of America’s democratic capitalism that provokes the protests but
the mere temptation that it represents.
This
formulation, however, sheds a new light on the causation problem. To say that
anti-Americanism is not caused by American policies and actions means two
things: it is not a result of specific American actions or cultural transfers,
and it is not primarily a response to the projection of a specifically American
identity, national interest, and so on. However if anti-Americanism is
decoupled from real policies and actions, it does not follow that it has
nothing to do with real experience. On the contrary, anti-Americanism does
indeed represent a response to genuine forces of historical change. What is at
stake, however, is not the remaking of the world in the image of America—a possible
working definition of “Americanization”—against which anti-Americans believe
they offer resistance, but rather the historical development in modernity
toward democratic capitalism, which during the twentieth century has transpired
disproportionately through American power and influence. Anti-Americanism is,
fundamentally, the rhetoric of opposition to this global historical process of
political and economic emancipation. Pretending to oppose American power,
anti-Americanism is in fact the ideology of opposition to the democratization of
politics and the liberalization of markets.
It
is in the nature of such political rhetoric that little value is placed on
consistency. Like other obsessive ideologies, anti-Americanism is internally
heterogeneous, and it draws on multiple cultural-historical currents. One can
however distinguish heuristically among different registers of
anti-Americanism, in particular the following three:
1. Predemocratic anti-Americanism expresses
an aristocratic (or imitatively aristocratic) disdain for the life of
democracy, deemed too ordinary, banal, and lacking in quality. America is taken
to represent the driving force of modernization as trivialization; nostalgia
for the golden age of a premodern world therefore turns into anti-Americanism.
Although these attitudes may have resonated among the members of the
traditional aristocracy, it is not that tiny social group that is important.
Rather this version of anti-Americanism has turned into a widespread hostility
particularly in cultural sectors. It has migrated largely into the arts,
generating, for example, the notion of America as lacking in high culture. Anti-Americanism
contrasts the allegedly low quality of American mass culture (Hollywood cinema)
with presumably higher standards of quality in Europe; or more generally, it
reduces the world to a simple opposition between American quantity and European
quality.
2. Communist anti-Americanism emerged
from the ideological apparatus of the Communist movement during the nearly seventy-five
years between the Bolshevik seizure of power and the collapse of the Soviet
Union. The global struggle between Russian interests, masked as Communist, and
the democratic agenda of the free world under U.S. leadership structured much
political and intellectual life for most of the past century. In the battle
with twentieth-century totalitarianism, the United States sometimes entered
into unholy alliances with undemocratic regimes; such is the complexity of politics.
Just as the United States entered into a strategic alliance with Stalin to
defeat Hitler, it had to back undemocratic regimes in the cold war struggle
against Soviet power.
Moreover,
it should surprise no one that foreign policies, like any government-generated
practice, sometimes become internally inconsistent. The point is that
inconsistencies such as these became targets for Communist propaganda and were
taken as evidence of Western hypocrisy. Yet with the collapse of the Soviet
empire, American foreign policy is gradually returning to its core values and
to the predisposition to support governments that are democratic or moving toward
democratization.6 (Marx himself largely
admired the dynamism of American capitalism and democracy and did not
participate in the anti-Americanism that came to be the hallmark of Communist
ideology in the twentieth century.)7 Although
the opening of the Berlin wall and the subsequent collapse of the Soviet empire
has meant the real collapse of the apparatus of Communist propaganda, the
discourse of Communist anti-Americanism remains in effect, particularly but not
only in former Communist circles. Where predemocratic anti-Americanism
typically turns into the cultural criticism of the United States, Communist
anti-Americanism still focuses especially on foreign policy disputes from the cold
war era: Vietnam, Cuba, Chile, Grenada, and so forth.
3. Postdemocratic anti-Americanism involves
current complaints that the United States remains reluctant to surrender
elements of its sovereignty in order to transfer them to international bodies.
Advocates of forms of international governance oppose the American insistence
on national independence as a precondition for the democratic expression of
popular will. Whatever the standing of international governance bodies may be,
they are in any case not elected institutions. At best, one might say that they
are institutions set up through treaties by several states; yet not only are many
of those states barely democratic, if at all, but the very presumption that a
state would significantly subordinate itself to the will of others in
institutions with no external control runs counter to liberal democratic
expectations. In addition, the prominence of nongovernmental organizations in
contemporary international debate highlights a sensitive distinction between
democratic sovereignty and private advocacy. Postdemocratic anti-Americanism
involves the assertion of the will of the experts, organized in partisan
advocacy associations, over the will of the people as expressed in electoral
processes.
These
three types of anti-Americanism can overlap and coexist within the same
material. In fact, one finds all three variants in the German responses to
September 11, which have been documented in a volume edited by the journalist
Henryk Broder: a collection of revealing statements by German writers, intellectuals,
and politicians. Because anti-Americanism is a cultural phenomenon, expressing
historical predispositions, political fantasies, and irrational ideologies, it
is appropriate that so much of the evidence derives from the cultural sector.
This is particularly true for predemocratic anti-Americanism, typically associated
with the aesthetic attitude of cultural elitism. This attitude is characterized
by a typically strained effort to maintain composure and to foreground a cool,
even cold, attitude, to suggest that the terrorist attacks were, ultimately,
not very important. Representatives of this version of anti-Americanism attempt
to demonstrate how they are simply too important to be concerned with the
suffering of the day, the significance of which they denigrate. The goal of
predemocratic anti-Americanism is to demonstrate a lack of concern, belying the
myth of universal solidarity with victims. A good example is found in the
comments of the award-winning and bestselling German author Martin Walser on
his experience of September 11:
I
had to give a reading in Bamberg [on Sept. 11]. I asked myself whether it would
really be appropriate to read from a novel called The Life of Love, but the organizer said we should proceed in
any case. And then I gave into a whim and said [to the audience]: “The
Americans are getting in my way again.” The audience was irritated, so I
explained that the premiere of my play Larger than Life Mr. Krott was scheduled for November
21, 1961 [sic], but it was cancelled due
to the Kennedy assassination. Then I gave my reading, and afterwards two
listeners said to me: “You helped us forget today’s events.” That was a
wonderful experience for me as an author.8
Walser’s
point is to demonstrate a studied lack of sympathy by hiding behind
aestheticism as an aristocratic posture. It is the work of art that counts, and
not the count of the victims. The point is not the appropriateness of having
proceeded with the reading on September 11 but Walser’s dismissing the conflict
as a humorous matter of American intrusiveness. For Walser, the importance of
his literature obviously and unquestionably overshadows any interest in the
human suffering of the attacks. The popular philosopher Peter Sloterdijk
similarly dismisses the scope of the tragedy. With an en passant reference
to the “catastrophe landscape” of the twentieth century, he diminishes
September 11 to a “barely noticeable, minor accident”9 Similarly,
during the first weeks after the attack, when one thought the body count was
considerably higher, a columnist of the taz, a popular left-of-center newspaper, eagerly
trivialized the event: “as regrettable as the death of seven thousand people in
New York may be, measured against what is taking place elsewhere in the world,
it is in comparison just a bagatelle.”10 In
all these examples, the scope of the American dead is denied through the appeal
to something always greater: an easy rhetorical trick.
Aside
from revealing a lack of human sympathy, this pseudo-aristocratic contempt for
American suffering strikes one as political misery. Desperate to diminish the
importance of September 11, these commentators blind themselves to the enormous
political consequences of the attacks, especially the transformed relationship
of the United States to the world. Not only do they remain untouched by the
human loss; their ideology prevents them from recognizing that September 11
would most likely change American foreign policy profoundly, for it was hardly
a trivial matter when the policy of preemptive attacks was subsequently
adopted. The more German opinion makers minimized September 11, the more they
contributed to the minimization of Germany’s standing in future foreign policy arrangements,
as became clear later in the context of the Iraq war. Yet this reduction in the
importance of Germany is a consequence of a consistently wrong arithmetic in
parts of the German public sphere: fifty dead in Jenin—the site of a pitched battle
between the Israeli army and Palestinian terrorists in the spring of 2002—was
denounced as a “massacre,” while even seven thousand American dead would have
been counted as a “bagatelle.”
Communist
anti-Americanism, the second variant, recycles motifs from cold war propaganda
and redirects them, once again, toward the United States. While predemocratic,
cultural anti-Americanism treats human suffering dismissively, Communist anti-Americanism
denounces suffering but blames it exclusively on the United States and world
capitalism. For example, a Party of Democratic Socialism leaflet distributed in
Hamburg commented on the September 11 attacks with the slogan “What goes around
comes around.”11 In other words, the terrorists were justified in
repaying like with like, meaning that the Americans got what they deserved.
More notoriously, another aspect of Communist vocabulary reappeared as well:
the pathos of the anti-Hitler rhetoric, turned against the United States—in particular
against George W. Bush. What the German minister of justice, Herta
Dau¨bler-Gmelin, said in her equation of Bush and Hitler was in fact not at all
exceptional; one can encounter similar remarks frequently in Germany. A
noteworthy instance involved a large banner held up during the demonstrations against
Bush in Berlin in May 2002, with pictures of Hitler pointing to the burning
Reichstag and of Bush in front of the crumbling World Trade Center. To make the
identification complete, they share the same cartoon bubble of speech:
This
attack means that our nation must set out on a long march to war and forget the
debilitating trust in civil liberties! But do not fear, my people, for this
just fight will only add to our glory!! And although this attack seems to be
made to order to make you forget my disputed seizure of power and to pave the
way for blind obedience to my orders, I want to have you believe that my
security forces had nothing to do with it. Thank you very much. See you later
in Poland or Iraq, and then around the world!!12
The
poster tells us little about Bush and Hitler but a good deal about the
political culture that could tolerate this sort of distorted representation.
For starters, of course, in a classic Communist manner, the antisemitic
character of Hitler’s rhetoric and National Socialism is simply expunged. In
addition, the conspiracy theory innuendo that American security forces carried
out the September 11 attack is clear. More generally, the equation of the legal
systems in Nazi Germany and contemporary America is striking: either it means
that the contemporary, post-Communist Germans imagine that Nazi Germany was
basically like the United States, and therefore not all that bad; or it implies
a grossly distorted view of the United States and the standing of civil
liberties. Yet we know that the German justice minister herself had described
the American legal system as “lousy.” Thus Communist imagery structures
anti-Americanism in two ways: in its denunciation of the historical American
defense of democracy against Soviet expansion and in its characterization of
capitalism, and especially the most developed capitalist society, the United
States, as fascist through the association with Hitler.
Although
the predemocratic and Communist variants of anti-Americanism represent residues
of obsolete political formations— no matter how these ideologies retain a
contemporary afterlife—postdemocratic anti-Americanism, the third model, reflects
an emerging divide: on the one hand, the widespread predisposition, perhaps
more in Germany than elsewhere, to shift decision making to supranational and
therefore undemocratic units—the European Union, the United Nations, an
international court—and on the other, the American insistence on the priority
of national sovereignty as an expression of popular will. The process of
sovereignty transfer corresponds both to the larger political and economic
pressure toward globalization and, simultaneously, to the logic of
bureaucratization: it is one more way to allow the deferral and dispersion of
decision making.
The
fact that Germany buys into this process of sovereignty transfer with special
enthusiasm reflects its own ambivalent relationship to its particularly
catastrophic national past and its impaired self-esteem (although there is
plenty of willingness to engage in symbolic self-assertion as long as the
opponent is the United States).13 Because Germany, in order
to overcome its past, is eager to shift decision making responsibility to a
supranational structure, it expects all other nations to similarly renounce
their national independence and dissolve into international, ultimately global,
governance structures.
In
the responses to September 11, this postdemocratic perspective emerged in
expressions of concern that U.S. policy inappropriately responds to domestic
constituencies. The (surely not incorrect) perception that American foreign
policy takes the opinion of the American electorate into account is the bone of
contention. In other words, there is an underlying assumption in parts of the
anti-American European public that policy, and in particular foreign policy,
ought to be decoupled from democratic political discussion and decision making
(i.e., diminishing the domestic public sphere). Because foreign policy has
international ramifications, it should, so the strange-but-true argument goes,
be separated from domestic democratic will formation and, presumably, be
shifted to international governance structures shielded from local political
sentiment. Apparently, American politicians should listen less to voters and
more to nongovernmental organizations. Thus the influential public intellectual
and cultural critic Klaus Theweleit wrote: “It is frequently overlooked that
Bush could only win the elections with votes from the Bible Belt, the votes of
fundamentalist Americans, religious fanatics. . . . And then Bush does not
understand when armed religious fanatics come back from other parts of the
world.”14
Leaving
aside the bizarre analogy of culturally conservative Christians to armed
terrorists, one notes Theweleit’s implicit objection to the notion that this
particular group, perhaps any particular group, should be able to participate
in the electoral process. Does he mean that Christian voters should be disenfranchised?
Yet if one assumes that fundamentalist Christians do indeed have the right to
vote—a right that Theweleit seems to dispute—then one cannot object to the
possibility that their votes might have consequences with political influence.
The same objection recurs even more frequently with regard to the Jewish vote,
evident in the tedious German paranoia regarding a “Jewish lobby” somehow
mysteriously steering American foreign policy.15 It
is this antisemitic content that regularly lurks behind the standard complaint
that U.S. Middle East policy is the function of domestic political concerns.
Yet
the notion that domestic politics ought to be excluded from foreign policy can
mean nothing else than decoupling foreign policy formation from the democratic
process. The logical conclusion would entail separating foreign policy from
democratic government and relocating it in an independent foundation of
objective experts: an absurd option, to be sure—but not that far from various
proposals for international governance. In any case, given this European
suspicion of the U.S. system as excessively democratic because of its
propensity to respond to domestic politics, it is only consistent that much
European public opinion does not proceed from a basic solidarity with
democratic states, particularly in the Middle East. In contrast, one of the
important successes of current U.S. policy has been the ability to focus
international attention on the urgency of democratization throughout that
region.16
These
three types of anti-Americanism may overlap and intermingle. Moreover they take
on specific colorations in different national contexts. French anti-Americanism
is more commonly marked by a cultural denigration of America; hence, for example,
Jean Baudrillard’s celebration of the September 11 terrorists as noble savages,
living authentically, in contrast to what he chose to refer to dismissively the
“banality” of American life.17 (This material is discussed
more closely in chapter 5).
Meanwhile
the geopolitical element in French discourse is typically more oriented toward
inventing space for France to imagine remaining among the key global players,
in contrast to German provincialism, eager to defer to Europe or the U.N.18 In Germany,
too, one can find cultural criticism and allegations about the low quality of
American culture. Communist-inspired accounts of twentieth-century history are
more common in Germany than in France (part of the East German legacy). More frequently,
however, German anti-Americanism is haunted by the anxieties of German national
history: the desperate need to relativize the Nazi past by imagining that the
United States, Israel, or both are equally criminal. Hence the long history of denouncing
America’s “everyday fascism” and—in the 9/11 discussions—the constant parallels
suggested between the Allied bombings in the Second World War and the air war
in Afghanistan: both, so the analogic argument goes, are wrong.
In
other words, lingering resentment about the U.S. role in the Second World War
contaminates the German judgment on current foreign policy. Evidence of current
American wrongdoing seems to provide Germans an absolution for their own past. What
then is the source of anti-Americanism? The first part of the answer is
negative: anti-Americanism is not the result of specific processes of cultural
or institutional transfer that could be construed to entail an
“Americanization.” Yet this does not mean that anti-Americanism is nothing more
than a free-floating discourse, with no relationship to real historical
processes. On the contrary—and this is the second part of the answer—anti-Americanism
is, fundamentally, an expression of hostility to societies of democratic
capitalism. This dynamic sort of social formation involves a set of
institutions that developed particularly through the history of Western culture
and its values, and it has flourished especially in the United States, which
has defended this model in the hot and cold wars of the twentieth century. Yet
democratic capitalism and its associated values are not narrowly American or
even exclusively Western. On the contrary, as a social model, it exercises
enormous attraction for populations around the world, one result of which is
immigration, as well as the remarkable ability of immigrant groups to integrate
with the U.S. polity quickly. Against cultural relativists, it is important to
assert that democracy is not a parochial artifact of American culture but
rather an objective potential of humanity, even if the United States has become
its primary, if sometimes reluctant, vehicle.
Anti-Americanism
is therefore not a response to specific policies or actions. It is not about
the spread of jazz or youth culture; nor is it, fundamentally, about the
bombing of Dresden, the proliferation of McDonald’s franchises in Paris, or
even the sanctions on Iraq, although each of these might be taken as a pretext
and each, one can add, might well be debated on its own terms.
Anti-Americanism, instead, involves a global judgment, an enormous stereotype,
driven by fears regarding democracy and capitalism. The fact that the American
model exercises such a magnetic attraction globally exacerbates the anxieties
among those who do not emigrate and especially among national cultural elites,
who resent their compatriots’ opting for an American life-course. But this
process, again, is not about the narrow assertion of American national interest
or the particular contents of American culture. Nor is the key issue
immigration, although the universal attraction of America—to peoples from very
different cultural backgrounds—is quite telling and proof of the universal
character of the specific set of values. The point is that the principles
objectified in the American Revolution—products, to be sure, of particular
cultural traditions—have proven to have universal appeal because they speak to
basic aspects of the human condition everywhere. “Here or nowhere is America,” spoke
Goethe’s Lothario in the novel Wilhelm
Meister’s Apprenticeship. By this he meant that the
political and social revolution of democracy, initiated in the American
Revolution, ought to be pursued in Germany, and not primarily through German
emigration to the United States.19 For Goethe, the structure
of emancipation—democratic government and free markets— modeled in the United
States was worthy of emulation elsewhere. It is that potential of freedom in
human history that anti-Americanism resists.
1.
See Russell A. Berman, “The Gulf War and Cultural Theory in the United
States
and Germany: Nationhood, Popularity and Yellow Ribbons,” in Berman,
Cultural Studies of Modern Germany: History, Representation, and
Nationhood (Madison:
University
of Wisconsin Press, 1993), 175–200.
2.
Jean-Franc¸ois Revel, L’obsession
anti-ame´ricaine: Son fonctionnement, ses
causes, ses consequences (Paris: Plon, 2002).
3.
Philip Zelikow and Condoleezza Rice, Germany Unified
and Europe Transformed:
A Study in Statecraft (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995).
4.
See Suzanne Zantop, Colonial
Fantasies: Conquest, Family, and Nation in Precolonial
Germany, 1770–1870 (Durham: Duke University Press, 1997), 18–42.
5.
Dan Diner, America in the Eyes of the Germans: An Essay on
Anti-Americanism,
trans.
Allison Brown (Princeton: Markus Wiener, 1996), 37.
6. The National Security Strategy of the United States,
September 2002, preface,
n.p.
(p. iii), http://whitehouse.gov.
7.
Diner, America in the Eyes of the Germans,
46.
8.
Cited in Henryk M. Broder, Kein Krieg,
Nirgends: Die Deutschen und der
Terror (Berlin: Berlin Verlag, 2002), 93. The correct date
for the Kennedy assassination
is
November 22, 1963.
9.
Ibid., 10.
10.
Ibid., 123.
11.
“So was kommt von so was.” Ibid., 200.
12. The Times of London, May 23, 2002, p. 17.
13.
Cf. Tom W. Smith and Lars Jarkko, “National Pride in Cross-National
Perspective,”
paper of the National Opinion Research Center (University of Chicago,
April
2001), http://www.issp.org/paper.htm.
14.
Broder, Kein Krieg, Nirgends, 186.
15.
William Safire, “The German Problem,” New York Times,
September 19,
2002,
A35.
16.
On the urgency of democratic reform in the Arab world, cf. Claire Nullis,
“Report:
Arab Economies Need Reform,” Washington
Times, September 8, 2002,
regarding
“Arab World Competitiveness Report” of the World Economic Forum.
17.
Jean Baudrillard, “The Spirit of Terrorism,” trans. Kathy Ackerman, Telos
121
(Fall 2001), 138; cf. Alain Minc, “Terrorism of the Spirit,” trans. Kathy
Ackerman,
Telos 121 (Fall 2001), 143–45;
and more generally, Philippe Roger,
L’ennemi ame´ricain: Ge´ne´alogie de l’antiame´ricanisme franc¸ais (Paris:
Seuil, 2002).
18.
Regarding provincialism, cf. Karl Heinz Bohrer, “Provinzialismus (II):
ein
Psychogramm,” Merkur 45,
no. 3 (March 1991), 255–61.
19.
Johann Wolfgang Goethe, Goethes Werke,
ed. Erich Trunz (Hamburg:
Christian
Wegner Verlag, 1962), VII, 431.
==============================
Anti-Americanism
in contemporary Europe has little to do with real policy disputes. Indeed, it
has little to do with reality at all. On the contrary, it follows a topsy-turvy
logic of obsessions driven by European fantasies about America. Drawing on long-standing
cultural traditions rather than on contemporary conditions, anti-Americanism is
trapped in a world of imagination. It is ideological in the sense that the
ideals to which it adheres are never tested against hard facts. Chapter 2
explored how anti-Americanism is divorced from reality. This chapter discusses
the consequence of this divorce: a political culture disconnected from the real
world of facts and actions. In order to explore this aspect of
anti-Americanism, it is necessary first to reflect on the standing of conflict
in politics and culture. Against that background, this chapter proceeds to
examine anti-Americanism’s political instinct, its opposition to wars in the
name of democracy, and its predisposition to maintaining the repressive peace
of authoritarian regimes—the classical politics of appeasement. This political
instinct has historical roots in the age of totalitarianism, but it is
amplified, as will be shown, by the pursuit of an emerging European identity:
the real voice behind the curtain of the anti-American Oz.
Politics
typically involves conflicting interests, be it a matter of competition among
individuals, parties, or states. The opposition of friend and foe in the
international arena can grow into an enmity that takes the form of a dramatic
scene, a confrontational face-off of two opponents. Accusation, recrimination,
and attack unfold on the stage of doubled adversariness. It is doubled because
the initial carrier of enmity, one side in the dispute, projects hostility on
to the other, presuming that the opponent maintains a symmetrical counterview.
The participant in the relationship of enmity assumes that the hostility is
equally shared by the opponent. The drama of conflicting relations is therefore
normally assumed to be a symmetrical arrangement. Political theory offers
alternative characterizations of conflict: either as an inescapable “state of
nature,” as an existential and irreducible struggle between irreconcilable
foes, or as a precondition to an equally dramatic consensus-formation in a
public sphere oriented toward compromise. The former model describes permanent
war; the latter, the pursuit of a perpetual peace. As different as these
outcomes are, the two alternatives and the gradations between them share an
assumption: the substantiality of the opposition (i.e., the suggestion that a
real, existence-defining conflict of interests underlies the hostility, whether
the interests are religious or material, cultural or economic). In such a
framework, enmity is understood to be the expression of conflict between
genuine opponents. Real-world differences are presumed to be the underlying
cause of political struggle.
Yet
it is worth considering another sort of case, where conflict is not symmetrical
in this sense and where prior or objective grounds are not the true cause of
hostility. As was argued in chapter 2, anti-Americanism in fact follows its own
ideological logic rather than genuinely conflicting interests. It is a cultural
phenomenon rather than a rational pursuit of policy. When hostility results
from such internal processes rather than from external conditions, the
insinuation that the opponent is driven by symmetrical enmity amounts to little
more than a fiction. By inventing the other as the enemy, one in fact ascribes
to the other the sentiments that are above all one’s own: I hate you so you
must hate me. Yet in such a case, where the imputation of hostility is a
fiction, the explanatory model of genuinely symmetrical enmity turns out to be
wrong. It is now more a matter of an ideological strategy designed to justify
hostility than an accurate description of an objective clash of interests. In
contrast to the forms of hostility that result from a real-world interest conflict,
other forms are the consequence of solely endogenous processes, all on one side
of the conflict. This asymmetrical model requires an alternative explanation.
A
primary anger in one party turns into anger at the world and only then finds
its target. This hostility should be judged not as a response to what the
opponent may have done, since the opponent is only a belated discovery. This
sort of hostility, on the contrary, is an expression of an internal cultural or
psychological process that requires the invention of a threat: an imagined
enemy representing the fictive danger required to sustain a troubled identity.
The image of the enemy is not the result of a real opposition but acts instead
as a mechanism to confirm the identity of the group. The enemy, in this sense,
is just a scapegoat, and the vilification of the scapegoat confirms the cohesion
of the community. The discourse of enmity, the sharply contoured
external-oriented narrative of hostility, turns out to be largely internally
driven; rather than describing an external world, it plays a role in the
construction of identity. Hostility, in such cases, is not about the enemy but
about the self. It involves an animus that predates the encounter with the presumed
enemy. Instead of a model in which a real opponent elicits a hostile response,
there is an internally generated anger, which only subsequently finds an object
to oppose. This is the case for European anti-Americanism: it is not a matter
of a plausible response to a real threat but rather the construction of an external
enemy in order to maintain the coherence of an identity for Europe.
This
argument concerning an endogenous or subjective hostility is not meant to
pertain to all conflicts. In other cases, tragedy and opposition do exist and
lead to real-world struggle. Here, however, it is a matter of conflicts that
are primarily subjective, driven by the internal logic of a cultural or
psychological need to find an opponent, rather than by a confrontation with a particular
opponent in an objective competition for a specific good. In the case of a
subjective hostility, the passion of belligerence, be it on the individual or
collective level, is ultimately separate from and prior to the choice of the
target of vilification. In political propaganda, this is precisely the dynamic
that George Orwell described so masterfully in 1984: mass sentiment would be channeled into
hatred for ever-shifting opponents for reasons that had little to do with those
opponents and everything to do with ensuring the stability of the totalitarian
political culture. Hatred becomes a free-floating instinct, available for redirection
toward whatever object is most expedient. The ritual denunciation of the
opponent may refer to distant circumstances, but it serves a purpose closer to
home. It has ultimately nothing to do with the vilified opponent’s real
existence, about which it prefers to remain largely ignorant and uninformed. Because
it depends on this distance from and denial of facts, this sort of mind-set
unleashes a continuing process of reality loss. The drama of enmity is
therefore false drama, as we can explore in the case of current European
anti-Americanism.
To
say that European anti-Americanism lacks a genuinely dramatic scene means that
it is not a reciprocal conflict between equal opponents. Anti-Americanism
cannot be explained as part of a mirror-image hostility. There is, to be sure,
some diffuse blowback, moments of anti-European hostility in the United States,
but it is hardly ever on the scale of European anti-Americanism. The silly case
of “freedom fries” is about as exciting as it gets: there are no anti-European
demonstrations, no burnings of French or German flags, no angry mobs with
pitchforks and tractors in front of Louis Vuitton boutiques or BMW dealerships.
American “anti-Europeanism” is not an equal partner but only an anemic
afterthought to the European spectacles. Europe is hardly a matter of regular
concern for the American public, whereas the United States represents an object
of constant obsession for the anti-American mind: an omnipresent and omnipotent
opponent. The asymmetry is evident in the imbalanced structure of transatlantic
name-calling. Former French foreign minister Hubert Vedrine’s complaint about
the “simplistic” character of American foreign policy or German justice minister
Herta Da¨ubler-Gmelin’s blunder equating Bush and Hitler generated irritation
and bemused curiosity in America, but these remarks quickly became yesterday’s
news; in contrast, Donald Rumsfeld’s comment on old and new Europe elicited
outrage and vitriol. A raw nerve had been touched, and European intellectuals
showed themselves eager to be provoked by an American secretary of defense.
Facing that real enemy, the non-European, old grudges melted away, and Jacques
Derrida and Ju¨rgen Habermas, philosophers on two sides of the Rhine who have
spent their careers attacking each other, promptly marched shoulder to shoulder
against the perceived American threat. Where sober criticisms of Rumsfeld or
American defense policy might have been plausible, the heavy hitters of the
European spirit replied with the crude weapons of cultural denunciation and
fantastic imagery that have characterized the anti-American mentality.1
Anti-Americanism
is not a reasoned response to American policies; it is the hysterical surplus
that goes beyond reason. That difference is evident in the constant recycling
of anti-American images that have a history that long antedates current policy.
The traditional European response to the new world and the United States has,
for centuries, involved themes of savagery, violence, and excess power, as well
as the anxieties generated by capitalism and democracy.2 These
stale images recur in the current discourse with stereotypical regularity. Yet
if the animus predates the policy, then the policy is clearly not the cause but
only the pretext, and the animus itself is prepolitical. Moreover, the
obsessive mentality of anti-Americanism shows up in countries with very
different experiences of the United States: Germany against the background of
an occupation that was never perceived as a liberation (and certainly elicited
no street celebrations), and France with the history of liberation but no
occupation. Two different menus leave the same taste in the mouth, as if the
flavor had a life of its own.
Yet
this separation of the affect of enmity from hypothetically objective causes
explains why the anti-American perception of the present is marked by the
regular loss of factual grounding and a nearly hermetic imperviousness to
events. Reality disappears. Hence the predisposition to disbelieve any reports
of real American success in the Afghanistan or Iraq wars, to denounce
pro-American Iraqis, and to exclude any information that does not fit into a
narrowly constructed myth: “nothing can shake it in its inner certitude,
because it is imprisoned in its safe world—because it is incapable of
experiencing anything”— thus the literary critic Georg Luka´cs, writing nearly
a century ago on the problem of “abstract idealism.” His characterization precisely
fits the substance of the anti-American mentality.3 In this
vein, one has to count the willingness of the mainstream European media to
treat the Iraqi information minister as a plausible source, until the very end,
while at the same time directing an unrelenting skepticism toward any signs of
coalition victory or Iraqi celebrations. Because the anti-Saddam Iraqis
disappointed the European anti-Americans, it was claimed that they did not
exist or, at best, were funded by Americans. This sort of fantastic thinking
with regard to the Iraq war, however, involves the very same reality denial
that characterized another episode, the response to the September 11 attacks:
the grotesque suggestions of hidden conspiracies or a mere media spectacle or—perhaps
most common—the European notion that it was not that bad after all. Reality
that does not match politically correct opinion cannot exist. Uncomfortable
facts and uncomfortable opinions are equally disallowed. The sort of debate
that has raged through the American public and press was just absent in much of
Europe.
For
anti-Americanism, the issue is not facts, to which one might respond
critically, but an obsession, an internally generated hostility, with no link
to the real world. Hence the predilection to denial: the Iraqis are not
celebrating, Al Qaeda did not attack the Twin Towers, the infidels are not in
Baghdad. Because of this separation of ideology from reality, images take over,
propagandistic targets of enmity, negatively charged icons. A telling case in
point is the anti-American journalism of the Indian writer and activist
Arundhati Roy. Obviously, Roy cannot be taken as an example of a typical
European intellectual, but she has achieved a particular celebrity status in
the European press, from the Manchester
Guardian to the Frankfurter Allgemeine, which has published her
anti-American essays. This prominence gives her writings a symptomatic
significance (i.e., they can tell us something about the anti-American
mentality).
Roy’s
style entails the rhetoric of antipathy, strings of stereotypical denunciations,
devoid of reasoned argument and sprinkled with targets of hatred. It is,
especially, a language that relies on derogatory personifications that serve to
focus the reader’s hatred. In one essay, for example, she arbitrarily conjures up
an otherwise unidentified “marrowy American panelist,” and in another she
points with disgust at an equally anonymous figure “who rolls his R’s in his
North American way.”4 Neither of these figures
plays any other role in her narratives, except to provide a negative image. Are
they real people or merely invented? We never know, but Roy deploys these
gratuitous fictions as objects of disdain, as if a marrowy physiognomy and a
North American accent—rather than policy—were the true affront. Her writing
will be discussed at greater length below in chapter 5 in relation to the
anti-Americanism of the movement against globalization.
At
this point, however, the concern is less Roy’s more elaborate ideology than the
fact that she is celebrated in the anti-American press and what this tells us
about the ideology of anti-Americanism. For example, in the opening of her
essay on “Mesopotamia,” of April 2, 2003, in the Manchester Guardian, she conjures up the
“adolescent American soldiers [who] scrawl colorful messages in childish
handwritings” on missiles, and she dwells with a sort of lascivious interest on
one private she saw in a CNN interview who “stuck his teenage tongue all the
way down to the end of his chin.” Her point is hardly sympathy with these
“teenagers” who find themselves in a war—a plausible antiwar stance, concern
for young people pulled into battlefield danger—but rather an explicit contempt
for Americans, described as infantile, and their silly teenage behavior: this,
she suggests, is the face of the enemy. What she subsequently musters as
pseudoargument in the course of her diatribe is only secondary to the imagistic
vilification of the opponent, classical propaganda, couched in a rhetoric
tailored for a European audience: Americans are unmannered and have poor
penmanship. The Indian author appeals to the elitism of European
anti-Americanism that sees Americans as lacking culture.
Her
focus on the motif of penmanship—irrelevant to policy substance but loaded as a
cultural stereotype—is symptomatic of the role of anti-Americanism in the
mainstream European press. A critique of Iraq policy is surely possible, but
there is a surplus here that goes beyond the ostensible political substance. It
is apparently not the policy but the poor manners that matter. It is not the
war that is the offense but the Americans themselves who are the real
provocation to Roy’s sensibility and to that of her readers. Opposition to the
war in Iraq is ultimately therefore interchangeable with opposition to all the
other aspects of American foreign policy. Opposition to the war does not lead to
anti-Americanism; rather anti-Americanism, the primary affect, elicits
opposition to the war. Iraq is really just one more item on a party platform.
If pushed, the anti-Americans might concede that Saddam, the Taliban, and
Milosevic were not particularly laudable (although we should not underestimate
the degree of pro-Saddam sympathy, especially in France), but they only became
issues because of that American foreign policy. Or to parse this even more
closely: it is not what Americans do— since, in the end, most would be hard put
to defend Milosevic, Saddam, and the rest—but the fact that it is Americans who
act and not Europeans. It is therefore not European pacifism, a principled opposition
to violence, that brings out the anti-American demonstrators but European
passivity and an appeasement mentality that recoils at the American ability for
action. The particular terrain where the action takes place becomes irrelevant.
For the anti-American mind-set, the world—Iraq, Afghanistan, the Balkans—is
always only a pretext, an emptied space, a blank sheet on which it tries to
scrawl its own childish message: childish because incapable of political
action.
What
provokes the anti-American is American activism: not that America plays a
particular role in the world but that it is in the world at all. Whatever the
American action, the anti-American denounces it, particularly when the action
is couched in a policy of defending the freedom to act, which in turn implies a
set of democratic values. The absence of freedom in particular locales—Iraq,
Afghanistan, the Balkans—is typically of concern only for tiny nongovernmental
organizations, not for mass protest movements, except when the United States
intervenes. There were never mass demonstrations in Paris, Berlin, or Barcelona
against Milosevic, the Taliban, or Saddam. There were never demonstrations for
regime change. The mass protest movement only emerged when the authoritarian
regime was challenged by the forces of democracy. Before the war, Iraq was noticed
only because of the sanctions policy—an evil attributed to the United
States—and never because of the regime’s character. In the context of the war,
however, the anti-American movement finds itself objectively, and often enough explicitly,
on the side of a dictator whom it had failed to criticize earlier; and it is
therefore even more scandalized by the American invocation of democracy. The
historical record shows that mass demonstrations in Western Europe in the
twentieth century more often than not have involved direct or indirect support
for authoritarian leaders in order to oppose the United States.
This
is an embarrassing political problem for the anti-American movement that
pretends to be progressive but keeps waking up in bed with dictators. It shows
willingness if not to celebrate, at least to tolerate, authoritarian regimes,
no matter how brutal, in order to refrain from any association with capitalism,
no matter how democratic. Any statism seems better than freedom if freedom
means a free market. This willingness to rally around dictators and ignore the
suffering in totalitarian regimes is an extraordinary feature of the political
culture of Western Europe. Even after the demise of Communism, the Communist
taboos hold sway, as does its irreparably damaged political culture. To be
sure, anti-Americanism today is not primarily a matter of old-style Communism,
but it is still stuck in the political culture of the Communist age. Old habits
die hard. In fact, the moral hypocrisy of the anti-American movement remains
hopelessly trapped in the classic scenario of political blackmail that defined
the limits of criticism in the century of totalitarianism. The traumatic scene
of the Hitler-Stalin pact— the willingness of the Left to fall in line and
oppose prospects for an antifascist war—continues to cast a long shadow on the possibility
of political protest. It still promotes the sorry political formula: tolerance
for an authoritarian peace, opposition to a democratic war. Hence the
willingness to oppose regime change in Iraq: better to side, objectively, with
Saddam Hussein than to support the American initiative for liberation. Peace at
any price.
Brecht
This
remarkable willingness to side with miserable regimes in order to avoid
supporting the democracy of the United States repeats the pattern of the left
in the years 1939 to 1941: the willingness to sacrifice substantive principles
in the name of political expediency. It is useful therefore to turn back to
that historical moment to see how one author in particular, the playwright Bertolt
Brecht—a Marxist, close to the Communist movement, and an exile from Hitler’s
Germany—viewed the political situation. Since he had every reason to fear the
Nazi regime, the peace between the two totalitarian dictatorships could hold no
appeal for him, despite his own Communist sympathies. Nonetheless, he had to
overcome many predispositions, the political correctness of his day, before
recognizing the possibility that the West—Western capitalist democracies and Great
Britain in particular—was ultimately worth supporting as a potential opponent
to Hitler.
For
a brief moment, the Marxist Brecht caught a glimpse of how capitalist democracy
represented a more plausible opponent to Nazi totalitarianism than did the
Communism of Stalinist Russia. In two passages in his journals, he managed to
work his way out of the politically correct Stalinist antiwar stance, the toleration
for repressive peace, and came to advocate the democratic war. Despite his standard
leftist starting points—anticapitalist, antibourgeois, antinationalist, and
antiwar—he was ultimately able to comprehend how a willingness to wage war, to
celebrate national identity, and to cultivate patriotism were desirable, at
least in the context of patriotism within a democracy and a war against
fascism. To do so, to recognize where the best hope lay for fighting Hitler,
required a profound shift in his political instinct to reject war as such. He
had to venture out of the ideological confines of Communism and its abstract idealism
to embrace instead the vision of a heroic engagement in the drama of struggle.
In order to fight for freedom, he had to escape from dogma. Brecht’s
successful, albeit brief, political opening provides a standard with which we
can measure the ideological character of anti-Americanism.
In
Scandinavian exile from Hitler’s Germany, Brecht watched Europe collapse:
“france fell at the maginot line, that underground 5-storey hotel, what an
embodiment of parasitical french capital investment!” (journal entry of June
28, 1940).5 After the French capitulation, would England fight?
Brecht had his doubts, in the context of the Hitler-Stalin pact and the
Communist opposition to war. In fact, Brecht had his own inclinations to oppose
both militarism and nationalism. After all, he had begun his writing career as
a schoolboy during the First World War with an attack on the Roman poet
Horace’s dulce et decorum
est pro patria mori, the famous verse declaring that it is sweet
and honorable to die for one’s homeland, and he was himself the author of the
fiercely antiwar poem “Legend of the Dead Soldier.” Having witnessed the
devastation that the First World War caused to Germany, especially to his
generation, Brecht was inclined to an antiwar position and, even in the changed
circumstances of 1940, he was an unlikely candidate to endorse the mission of
the English army. Yet despite his pacifist leanings and despite the Stalinist
tilt against war and against the Western democracies through the pact with
Hitler, Brecht began to explore the prospect for British participation in a
possible democratic war, even before the fall of France. These explorations involve
two key points where war and literature overlap.
Throughout
Brecht’s oeuvre, the Anglo-American world carries negative associations of
capitalism and crime, from the London of The Threepenny Opera to the Chicago of Arturo Ui, and
of course the elegiac poetry of the exile years in Hollywood. These same terms
of disparagement continue in contemporary anti-Americanism, so Brecht’s coming
to grips with England can be taken as an alternative resolution of some of the
same cultural problems: Brecht could come to embrace democratic England as a
force against Hitler in a way that today’s anti-Americans refuse to support the
United States in the war against Saddam Hussein. Of course, Brecht, who
cultivated a tough-guy image, felt some affinity with the masculine brutality
that he associated with England, but this predisposition stood increasingly under
the ideological censor of standard anti-militarism and Communist dogma. Trying
to come to grips with England, however, he gradually overcame this resistance,
at least partially.
In
order to understand England, the writer Brecht, not surprisingly, read literature
and history. In a remarkable journal entry of February 2, 1940, he reports on
his reading Thomas Macaulay’s essay on the early eighteenth-century poet Joseph
Addison. It is here that Brecht encounters the liberal revolutionary England,
in the wake of the Glorious Revolution of 1688, with its burgeoning public
sphere in which literature took on a prominent role. As Macaulay put it, “Now
the press was free, and had begun to exercise unprecedented influence on the
public mind. Parliament met annually and sat long. The chief power in the State
had passed to the House of Commons. At such a conjuncture, it was natural that
literary and oratorical talents should rise in value.”6 It
is hardly surprising that Brecht, the advocate of an engaged literature and a
political theater, would find this cultural model appealing, in constrast to
what Macaulay disparaged as the “servile literature of France,”7 with
its deep dependence on the power of the monarchy. Brecht concludes that English
literature is strong “because a national life existed and the bourgeoisie came
to power at an early stage”8—in contrast to German
backwardness, without nationhood and without a national market. In other words,
Brecht attributes the success of British literature to the vitality of
nationhood and the energy of the market economy of the “bourgeoisie.” Those are
certainly not the typical values associated with communism, and the Marxist
Brecht immediately glosses his own remark with an expression of surprise and
despair: “what criteria!” At odds with his past, he finds himself compelled to
reconcile his admiration for the English cultural achievement with an initial
distaste for the precondition of that same cultural success: liberal
capitalism. For it is precisely that market-based political economy that
supported the culture that—Brecht reports—promoted technological progress and
an empirical worldview and epistemology: German literature, he complains, is
backward and idealistic, whereas British literature is up-to-date and engaged
in the materiality of the real world.
Brecht
then proceeds to draw these points from the critical debate on Addison’s poem
“Campaign,” which celebrated the Duke of Marlborough’s defeat of the French and
Bavarian armies on August 13, 1704, at the Battle of Blenheim, a turning point
in the War of Spanish Succession. The more literary his argument gets, the more
pertinent it is for an analysis of political ideology. Thus, Brecht reports on
how Dr. Johnson applauded Addison’s use of concrete metaphors as exemplifying
the advantage of the particular over the general: instead of bland
generalizations or abstract connections, the comparisons are apt and grounded
in reality. For Brecht, this concreteness of Addison’s language and thought is
tied to a model of heroic individualism: the hero who acts in the real world,
instead of losing himself in cloudy vagueness. Addison’s praise poem of
Marlborough’s military success is therefore simultaneously a celebration of the
individualism of British liberty over the continental servitude of the
absolutist French state. To cite Addison on Marlborough’s army:
. .
. with native freedom brave The meanest Briton scorns the highest slave.9
For
Brecht reading Macaulay reading Addison, the eighteenth-century battle of
modern Britain against monarchist France represents a precedent for what Brecht
hopes would ensue: a campaign by Britain—and the United States—pursuing the
values of liberty and freedom against the oppressiveness of the continent.
German literature, in contrast, remains for Brecht effetely idealistic and
underdeveloped, fundamentally unable to compete with the cultural revolution
unleashed by the liberalizing dynamism of England.
Yet
Brecht remains hesitant: the values of freedom and capitalism, nationhood and
military strength are tough medicine for him to swallow, burdened as he is with
his Communist loyalties and Central European pessimism. However, the February
journal entry on Macaulay still preceded the fall of France. Once the Germans
were in Paris, suddenly the Nazi threat loomed much larger, and by August we
find him struggling again with his own resistance and hesitations. He reports
that he has “skimmed”10 Matthew Arnold’s edition of
Wordsworth—his underlining the brevity of his reading betrays an embarrassment to
have to admit that he has been reading this presumably conservative literature—but
he pushes immediately to the conclusion that it is dangerous “to lay down the
law,” which, in this context, means to condemn this literature as “petty
bourgeois”: the dogmatic judgment his Marxist aesthetic would most likely have
reserved for Wordsworth’s poem “She Was a Phantom of Delight.” In other words,
Brecht is announcing that the standard Marxist ideological rejection is wrong.
As
Robert Kaufman has shown, Brecht works out his own aesthetic agenda here;11 but
he is also working out a politics, a willingness to accept the progressive
character of a democratic capitalist culture personified by the British
citizen-soldier in wartime: “the individual petty bourgeois currently
patrolling the fields of england equipped with a shotgun and a molotov cocktail
(‘as used against tanks in the spanish civil war,’ so a general assured us on
the wireless).”12 Whom does the Marxist Brecht celebrate here? It is
not a mythic proletarian revolutionary or a Communist cadre but the really
existing citizen of a capitalist bourgeois society, who, moreover, carries the
emblem of the antifascist fight, a weapon from the Spanish Civil War. But if this
democratic and capitalist society has, as Brecht insists, a claim on a poetry
that can “conjure up situations more worthy of the human race,” he has
effectively retracted his youthful attack on Horace: it is, so it turns out in
the summer of 1940, proper to fight for one’s country, and poetry can provide
sweet comfort. Brecht has moved from support for the repressive peace to
approval of a war fought for democracy.
Brecht
goes on to comment on the poem at hand, Wordsworth’s “Phantom of Delight.” He
distances himself from Wordsworth’s suggestion that art serves only “to haunt,
to startle, and to waylay.” While Wordsworth seems to suggest that a poem is
only about romantic beauty, Brecht calls for poetry to do more. Nonetheless,
his comments follow the movement of the poem, which makes its way from a
ghostly “apparition” or “phantom” to the recognition of reality and then from
reality to an affiliation of art and freedom, or in Wordsworth’s words: “Her
household motions, light and free, / And steps of virgin liberty.” Tracing the
movement of the ideal apparition to the material embodiment of lived life,
Wordsworth’s poem in fact even goes beyond Brecht’s own materialism, beating
him at his own game:—unless one reads Brecht’s meditation on the urgency of
poetry for the soldier in the field as a commentary on the poem’s telos. It
was, one can conclude, a Wordsworthian “virgin liberty” that had fought in
Catalonia, and so Brecht hopes, the same spirit of liberty will rally to defend
England. Making freedom real is the beautiful: an aesthetic proposition where
Brecht and Wordsworth, the Communist and the romantic, overlap.
Brecht’s
engagement with English literature has multiple components: autonomy,
aesthetics, individualism, the mercantile ethos of capitalism, and the heroic
ethos of war. Facing the danger posed by the authoritarian state on the
continent, Brecht turned to the alternative: the parliamentary England of
Addison’s day that challenged Bourbon domination of the continent around 1700,
and, a century later, Wordsworth’s England of 1800 that defeated Napoleonic
imperialism. Would the English-speaking world similarly withstand the Nazi
threat of Hitler’s Festung Europa,
“fortress Europe”? Analyzing the British culture that could support the
democratic wars—the poetry of Addison and Wordsworth—Brecht comes to admire it,
even if he would never make it fully his own. Nonetheless, for the moment of
1940 at least, he could overcome his illiberal predispositions and express
esteem for the democratic petty bourgeoisie, hoping that British capitalism
would be able to live up to its historical legacy and act against fascism. His
admiration for the soldier in the field, radiant with the aura of Wordsworth
and the legitimacy of antifascism, is the diametrical opposite of Roy’s disdain
for the democratic soldier, with his childish scrawl and bad manners. The
passages show Brecht working toward a rapprochement with the liberal
institutions of England and the emancipatory character of bourgeois, which is
to say, capitalist, life: for this same substance, shifted to the United
States, today’s anti-American only has contempt.
Is
anti-Americanism an endogenous formation, the consequence of internal European
cultural processes, or does it reflect genuine differences between Europe and
the United States? This chapter began exploring the first model, according to
which the enemy is understood to be a retroactive construction, necessary for
the constitution of an identity. It followed that anti-Americanism had little
to do with reality, or with real conflicts, and much more to do with cultural
traditions and stereotypes. Yet Brecht’s reflections of 1940 suggest an
alternative account. At a particular point in history, he was able to shift
loyalties from one culture to another, from continental ideologies of dogma to British
liberalism and liberty. For all his Central European illiberalism (which is
shared by today’s European anti-American movements), he nonetheless imagined a
personal rapprochement with the enemy, the culture across the channel. Brecht,
the son of Augsburg, accepted Marlborough’s victory at Blenheim and all that
that implied—parliamentary ascendancy, commercial culture, military prowess as
a progressive force, and, ultimately, autonomy aesthetics. This was no longer a
one-sided story but a clash of civilizations; on the one hand, a “servile literature,”13 associated
with the authoritarian states of the continent, and on the other, a democratic
civic life prepared to defend itself. Brecht locates this militant democracy in
English culture; it is the same Anglo-American culture that is the target of
the anti-American mentality.
Yet
these two explanations seem to be mutually incompatible: either
anti-Americanism is the product of its own internal ideological fantasies or it
is the effect of real differences between Europe and the United States. The
model of an animus driven by internal concerns and therefore characterized by
the loss of external reality would presumably exclude the thesis of a realworld
distinction between the cultures of the Atlantic and the continent, between
commercial parliamentarianism on the one hand and regulatory regimes of state
authority on the other. If there is indeed a conflict between these two
orders—with social, cultural, and political implications—then it is less
obvious that the animus is merely the expression of an independent instinct. So
we face again the alternative between explanatory models for European
anti-American hostility as either symmetrical or asymmetrical.
When
anti-Americanism claims to be a response to specific American policies, it fits
the dramatic model: policy conflict produces hostility. Yet, as we have seen,
this self-presentation in fact typically invokes American policy only as a
pretext. Too many features of anti-Americanism as a rhetorical and cultural
phenomenon call this dramatic explanation into question. At best, it dwindles
into a matter of lyric drama, just so much fantasy and fairy tale. In this
sense, it is telling that European anti-Americanism succumbs repeatedly to its
own tales of Arabian nights: the warning that American policy will ignite the
“Arab street” with unforeseeable consequences. Yet this fiction has always
proven itself a projection, a European desire staged as a fantasy against an
Orientalist backdrop. The real issue of anti-Americanism is not the Arab street
but the streets of Paris and Berlin and, in particular, their masquerading in
exotic costumes as if they were the “Arab street.” Far from toppling states in
Jordan or Pakistan, the street demonstrations have only strengthened regimes in
France and Germany; indeed the anti-American marches in Europe have in effect
just been large progovernment rallies. The animosity toward the United States
can be projected onto the rest of the world because for the anti-American the
world has been emptied of meaning. The appeal to the Arab street involves no
empathy with the Arab world; on the contrary, that street is only invoked in
order to manipulate its image to carry out a European agenda, rather than to address
an American policy.
This
anti-Americanism has little to do with specific American policies. It is not
about changing American action in the Arab world but about distinguishing
Europe from the United States—that is, inventing a European identity as an
alternative to the United States. This anti-Americanism is therefore indeed endogenous
(a matter of European identity formation) and, ultimately, prepolitical (i.e.,
primarily cultural) as further shown by the inconsistencies in the local form
it takes in different venues. If the point were a reasoned opposition to a
specific policy, then one would expect the same argument to be made in
different European countries. Instead, the mentality involves considerable local
variation. In Germany, one finds the plethora of metaphors designed to
exculpate the German past: Bush as Hitler, the bombing of Baghdad as the
bombing of Dresden, the attack on the World Trade Center as the burning of the
Reichstag. These displacements in fact tell us little about the United States,
but they indicate a disturbed relationship to the troubled German past and a
desire to resolve it through the expression of animosity. These metaphors make
little sense elsewhere. In France, in contrast, a much more pronounced
antisemitism contributes to the movement culture, including physical violence,
in ways (for various reasons) less likely in other European countries. In
addition, the French imperative to position itself against the United States
has to do with its own history and its fantasies about a lost world-power
standing (the same power, after all, that Marlborough defeated at Blenheim).
Yet
none of this has much to do with American policies. The real goal is a European
identity. Beyond the fantasies or the caricatures, we should look at the
various components of real anti-Americanism, its political categories, to
understand how it plays a role in the invention of a unified Europe:
anti-Americanism as a European fantasy exercise. However, at the same time, and
beyond local national variations, this unified Europe, which is coming into
shape precisely under the ideological umbrella of anti-Americanism, does
represent a real-world alternative and is, objectively, in a fundamental and
exogenous conflict with the United States. There is a drama, so to speak, a
polar opposition, between the United States and Europe, but it is one that the
anti-Americans barely comprehend. The anti-American mass movement that opposes
the United States understands itself as a progressive force in history and points
an accusatory finger, therefore, to the pacts with the devil that the United
States made in the cold war. (Its prepolitical moralism precludes its facing up
to the difficult complexities of a lesser-of-two-evils choice.) However, the
Soviet empire is gone now, the cold war is over; and the United States has
shifted aggressively to a foreign policy of liberalization, a fundamental
challenge to authoritarian regimes, and, in a deep historical sense, a return
to the principles that underlay the rational freedom of Addison, whom Brecht could
so appreciate. It is that liberalization that emergent Europe resists: no
regime change, ever. Anti-Americanism is the ideology of maintaining the status
quo while also providing a foil against which Europe can define itself.
Anti-Americanism
has emerged as an ideology available to form a postnational European identity.
In that sense, it is endogenous: not a response to an outside threat but an
aspect of European political and cultural transformation. For the European Union
to be credible, it has to carry some meaning and stand for more than a
bureaucratic apparatus. Yet Europe has no ideal content of its own; its failure
to show leadership in the Balkans in the early 1990s—1992 was to have been the
“year of Europe”—robbed it of the opportunity to define itself credibly through
the values of human rights and democracy. It therefore has to define itself
negatively, against outsiders, through the deployment of caricatured opponents.
Anti-Americanism fills this ideological gap. In place of the nationalist
anti-immigration mood of the 1990s, anti-Americanism permits a generalized European
hostility toward the paradigmatic nation of immigrants. Europeans can therefore
indulge in xenophobia without nationalism.
For
individual European nations, the price of entry into a unified Europe is the
gradual renunciation of national substance; this is a painful process, even in
Germany, the country most eager to shed any remaining national legacy. This
price includes a suppression of intra-European enmities. The European past is invoked
as teaching that war must be avoided at all costs. Therefore: peace at any
price, even repressive peace, and a prohibition on regime change, which was the
common denominator between the governments and the European street.
Anti-Americanism is the other side of the coin of appeasement. These are, moreover,
not opportunistic positions but the necessary consequence of suppressing
European nationhoods. As the irreversible transfer of authority to the
supranational organizations of the European Union takes place, a deeply felt
democracy deficit ensues. It is the direct result of the priority of regime
(not to be changed) over nation (scheduled for elimination): more and more of
European life is regulated by powers beyond electoral control or even public
transparency. The political theorist Carl Schmitt long ago identified the
process by which the power of democracies shifts increasingly into the
undemocratic and arcane realms of closed committees and bureaucratic decision making.14 Unified
Europe is the prime example of this process. It has burgeoned into the
generalized postnational and postdemocratic regime of multilateralism:
government less by election and more by regulation. The international form of
the same principle is represented by the United Nations (regarded by Europeans,
strangely, as carrying some moral authority); domestically, it implies the
bureaucratic social state and the regulated economy, impervious to reform.
Anti-Americanism,
as the endogenous ideology formation necessary for European unification, does
however ultimately confront an alternative—the United States—and enter into conflict
with it. Both explanatory models hold. The objective substance of the conflict
involves the opposition between multilateralism and unilateralism. Leaving
aside the polemical points to be scored regarding Germany’s unilateralism in
prematurely opting out of an Iraq campaign (regardless of a potential U.N.
decision) and similarly bracketing the character of the French role in the U.N.
and the French abuse of this organization, one can nonetheless recognize that
the choice between unilateralism and multilateralism points far beyond the
technicalities of international relations. A difference between two fundamentally
distinct cultural worldviews is at stake. Multilateralism involves, by
definition, an infringement of individual prerogative and implies the deferral
of responsibility to a regime of committees, which—as the political theorist
Hannah Arendt would have put it—is a responsibility of no one. It has a
consequence in domestic policy as well as international relations: the overcoming
of egoism. The association of the United States with unilateralism, in
contrast, involves a different notion of liberty, outside the state and outside
the suprastate. The European vitriol directed at the United States allows
Europeans to enter the European community. It is however simultaneously—and dramatically—the
expression of hostility to independence, both individual and national, and on a
deeper cultural level, the distorted expression of the pain of having had to
surrender local purviews to a supranational bureaucracy. Forced to renounce their
particular pasts and their national instincts, Europeans condemn as archaic
American nationhood, looking at it all the same with wistful jealousy. The
enmity directed at the United States externalizes the pain of loss and protests
against the unfairness: why has history permitted Americans to maintain a
national identity, while Europeans feel compelled to surrender theirs? Mass
demonstrations—much more a European form than an American—are the appropriate
ritual for this identity loss, in which grief over one’s fate is transformed
into rage against another’s fortune.
A
different and better Europe, one that lived up to the best of its past and
pursued its aspirations, might tell a different story. After all, it was once
liberty that led the people, even in Paris. Instead, today, anti-Americanism
serves as a peculiar social psychology, based on the collectivistic identity
formation that provides an antireformist ideology for European unification. European
anti-Americanism is the primary cultural and ideological substance for the
otherwise only bureaucratic process of European unification. This was quite
clear in German Chancellor Gerhard Schroeder’s election campaign: opposing
American policy in Iraq was part of opposing amerikanische Verhaeltnisse (American
conditions in general), meaning economic reform and deregulation. It remains to
be seen whether Schroeder in Germany or the Chirac-Raffarin team in France will
be able to cash in on their anti-American popularity in order to pass unpopular
economic reform. The more likely outcome is at best a minimally modified
version of the status quo. The opposition to regime change is, in the final
analysis, about preventing any change in the welfare-state regimes of Western
Europe. Better indolence than independence.
Having
probed the origins of European anti-Americanism as part of the identity
formation of unified Europe, we can recognize the alternative models of the
post–cold war world, which replace the myth of the Atlantic community of
values. During the missile debate of the 1980s, Cornelius Castoriadis criticized
the anti-NATO peace movement’s willingness to subordinate all values to peace.15 Not
all qualities of life should be sacrificed in order to maintain peace. The
terrain is not much different in the context of the war on terror. A European
predisposition to accept the status quo and to do nothing rather than to take
risks, no matter how dire the situation, contrasts with an American
predisposition to assert independence and insist on a responsibility to act,
individually and as a nation. It is, however, ultimately not the American
actions themselves but the European inability to act that provokes
anti-American rage.
1.
Cf. Ju¨rgen Habermas, et al.,“Das alte Europa antwortet Herrn Rumsfeld,” Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, January 24,
2003, 33.
2.
All this has been amply documented in various studies. Cf. Dan Diner, America in the Eyes of the Germans: An Essay on Anti-Americanism,
trans. Allison Brown (Princeton: Markus Wiener, 1996); Philippe Roger, L’ennemi americain: Ge´ne´alogie de l’antiame´ricanisme franc¸ais (Paris:
Seuil, 2002); Susanne Zantop, Colonial Fantasies:
Conquest, Family, and Nation in Precolonial Germany, 1770–1870
(Durham: Duke University Press, 1997).
3.
Georg Luka´cs, The Theory of the Novel: A
Historico-Philosophical Essay on the Forms of Great Epic Literature,
trans. Anna Bostock (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1971), 99.
4.
Arundhati Roy, Power Politics (Cambridge:
South End Press, 2001), 36, 41.
5.
Bertolt Brecht, Journals 1934–1955,
trans. Hugh Rorrison (New York: Routledge, 1996), 71.
6.
Thomas Babbington Macaulay, “The Life and Writings of Addison,” in Macaulay, Essays on Milton and Addison (New York:
Longmans, Green, and Co., 1900), 112.
7.
Ibid., 115.
8.
Brecht, Journals 1934–1955, 69.
9.
Joseph Addison, “The Campaign, A Poem to His Grace the Duke of Marlborough,
1705,” The Penn State Archive of Samuel Johnson’s Lives of
the Poets, ed. Kathleen Nulton Kemmerer, http://www.hn.psu.edu/faculty/kkemmerer/
poets/addison/campaign.htm.
10.
Brecht, Journals 1934–1955, 90.
11.
Robert Kaufman, “Aura, Still,” October, no. 99
(Winter 2002), 73–74, note 46.
12.
Brecht, Journals 1934–1955, 91.
13.
Macaulay, Life and Writings of Addison,
115.
14.
Cf. Carl Schmitt, The Crisis of Parliamentary
Democracy, trans. Ellen Kennedy (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985).
15.
Cornelius Castoriadis, Devant la
guerre (Paris: Fayard, 1981).
==============================
Anti-Americanism has multiple dimensions. After
examining the German data in chapter 1, in chapter 2 we explored several
cultural and historical variants of anti-Americanism: first, an antimodern,
predemocratic tradition; second, the legacy of communist ideology; and third, a
contemporary, postdemocratic hostility to national sovereignty as such. Each
version pushes anti-Americanism in a different direction. Chapter 3 looked at the
tension between fantasy and reality in anti-Americanism, its ideological
standing, and the role that anti-Americanism plays in the definition of an
emerging identity for unified Europe. It is, however, obvious that current
anti-Americanism has erupted in relation to the two Iraq wars. Although the
various discourses of anti-Americanism refer to many issues, both political and
cultural, it was clearly the confrontation between Washington and Baghdad that
fueled the anger of the European street. Anti-Americans denounce the United
States largely because it deposed Saddam Hussein.
The first Iraq war was fought to end the
Iraqi occupation of Kuwait. The second Iraq war was fought to end the Iraqi regime.
Both wars, however, were fought in terms of a metaphor: Saddam as Hitler. As
this chapter will show, the terms of the metaphor shifted over time. At first
the analogy had the narrow meaning of pointing out the unprovoked annexation of
foreign territory: just as Hitler had invaded Czechoslovakia, Saddam had
swallowed Kuwait, both transgressions against internationally recognized
borders. Quickly, however, even during the first Iraq war, the metaphor came to
signify the brutality of the Iraqi regime or, rather, the brutality of the
Iraqi regime in its occupation of Kuwait. During the second Gulf war, the use
of the metaphor became more emphatic: the brutality of the Iraqi regime to the
Iraqi population itself and, especially, to ethnic minorities (e.g., the Kurds,
the treatment of whom displayed a genocidal character). Moreover, the nature of
the international threat posed by Iraq changed. Rather than being viewed as a
local bully endangering its neighbors, Iraq came to be understood as the
carrier of weapons of mass destruction, representing a much graver danger to
countries much further away. On the one hand, the global threat associated with
Iraq echoes the classical totalitarian aspiration to world domination; on the
other, it is the function of a changed security perception after September 11.
The question of Iraq is central to the
understanding of current anti-Americanism for two different reasons. As noted,
the Iraq wars are the primary casus belli of the anti-Americans against the
foreign policy of the United States. On a deeper level, however, the metaphor
of Saddam as Hitler can lead us to a better understanding of what is at stake.
For large parts of the American public, a war against totalitarianism remains
just and worthwhile. For large parts of the public in Europe—the continent that
incubated the two totalitarianisms that dominated the last century—a preference
for appeasement prevails, and this difference turns into anti-Americanism.
However, the willingness to accommodate
reprehensible regimes is not only a European phenomenon, and clearly
significant parts of the American public were opposed to the war. It is as if
the judgment on totalitarianism had somehow softened since the collapse of
Communism: not that one can find many defenders of the great dictators of the
past but simply that the condemnation of Nazism and Communism no longer
convincingly provides the orientation for the moral compass of many. So it is
not surprising that George W. Bush’s characterization of the Ba’ath regime as
“evil” could be viewed as simplistic by a contemporary sensibility reluctant to
distinguish between right and wrong, especially in Europe. It is not that
anyone mounted much of a positive defense of Saddam Hussein’s regime, but there
was clearly reluctance to challenge it: Would it not be more comfortable just
to ignore brutal regimes? Not everyone supported a war against Hitler, so it is
not surprising to find an appeasement camp with regard to the metaphoric
Hitler. The Iraq wars posed the question of totalitarianism, both in terms of
the metaphor of Saddam as Hitler and in terms of the real character of the
regime, as will be discussed in this chapter. However, the wars also revealed
the complex relationship of outsiders, so-called world opinion, to totalitarian
regimes: though some witnesses can muster the resolve to confront evil, there
is always a large appeasement camp with a strong desire to ignore, minimize, or
even accommodate Hitler, Saddam, and their ilk. Therefore the historical
question of totalitarianism is inextricably related to the contemporary
question of moral judgment. Examining the metaphor of Saddam as Hitler allows us
to reexamine the judgment on totalitarianism and thereby explore important
inclinations in contemporary political culture. Germans born after 1945
sometimes asked their parents what they had done under the Nazi regime. Why had
they failed to resist? History will eventually pose the same question to those who
would have preferred to protect Saddam’s regime from change.
Weimar Germany has long stood as the prime
example of a democracy that failed and turned into the cradle of
totalitarianism. This teleology from Weimar to Hitler anticipated the many failed
democracies of the twentieth century, and it stands as a cautionary note for
current and future democratization prospects. Today we continue to ponder
Weimar culture to understand the vulnerability of democracy and the potential
for totalitarian outcomes. Nazi Germany casts multiple shadows on the
mass-murderous landscape of the twentieth century, and Weimar remains pertinent
as long as mass destruction haunts the modern world.
Yet the paradigmatic significance of the
failure of Weimar and the establishment of Nazi Germany is frequently obscured or
distorted by certain misconceptions, which deserve interrogation. First, it is
an illusion to believe that there is an intellectually viable strategy to
identify this Nazi modernity as distinctively belonging to a “right,” and
therefore different from a “left,” modernity in a substantive way that is more
than merely about the externals of party affiliation. There were left and right
strands within National Socialism itself, and in any case what made the regime
so central to the twentieth century was its totalitarian and genocidal
character, which exploded the leftright mold.
Second, it is equally misguided to approach
the Nazi regime primarily as a cultural (and especially as an
aesthetic-cultural) phenomenon, associated with the establishment of something reasonably
described as cultural hegemony. This cultural approach explicitly avoids
politics as well as the degradation of politics into coercion and violence.
Moreover the solely cultural approach to totalitarianism quickly runs into the
temptations of cultural relativism, as if the Nazi worldview were just one
possible choice among many, and therefore not subject to condemnation.
Finally, perhaps because of the growing
distance from 1945, an underlying historicist tone has emerged that suggests that
the Nazi era belongs to a completed past, a period in some once-upon-a-time
epoch that has little to do with our contemporary condition. In this case, it
would follow that the experience of that era has little pertinence to our
thinking and institutions and that the totalitarian and mass-destructive
potential played out in Germany in the 1930s and 1940s has no lessons for our
contemporary predicament.
These three predispositions—accepting the
conceptual viability and relevance of the left-right distinction, particularly regarding
the emergence of the Nazi regime; the privileging of a cultural explanation and
the attendant cultural relativism; and the historicizing distance indicating a
diminished urgency to the question of totalitarianism—exemplify intellectual
failings in the age of a relativist sensibility. To cut through some of these current
misconceptions and recapture the standing of Hitler’s Germany for political
theory, it is productive to dwell on the current political metaphor, Saddam as
Hitler, which can help us ferret out issues in the nexus of totalitarian
regimes, political violence, and mass culture. Comparing Nazi Germany and
Ba’athist Iraq, we can try to refocus the question of totalitarianism and its
implication for political culture. In particular, this comparison can help
clarify the three problems mentioned above and address certain lacunae in
contemporary discussions of both regimes.
Regarding the left-right distinction: it
makes little sense to claim that Nazi Germany was somehow of a “right” and that
Stalinist Russia was then of a “left.” Perhaps this distinction holds in the
nuances of their respective discourses, but the overwhelming feature of
totalitarianism, the destructive power of the unlimited state—the diametrical
opposite of any ethos of limited government—outweighs those distinctions in
style, and in any case, that destructiveness was not the function of being “right”
or “left.” As long as we pretend that National Socialism was of the right, then
the parallel between the totalitarianisms of Hitler and Stalin is missed, and
the history lesson of the twentieth century just becomes political bias.
Saddam’s Iraq is a case in point for the obsolescence of the political
designations of left and right; to paraphrase a familiar slogan, it was neither
left nor right but just terrible. It derived directly both from Hitler and Stalin
in specific intellectual, political, and symbolic terms. Like both, it involved
a regime in which the personality of the leader was central and stood in a
dialectical relationship to a manipulative ideology of the mass: in the
totalitarian world, the call for “mass cultures” implied the empowerment of
great dictators.
The case of Iraq also calls into question
cultural approaches to the Nazi regime, which naturally ascribe a central
analytic standing to “Nazi culture.” Was the contemporary credibility of the
totalitarian regime genuinely a matter of a cultural consensus achieved through
the successful dissemination of a plausible belief structure? Shall we really
believe that the Nazi film and propaganda apparatus successfully convinced the
German public that all was right with their world? No totalitarian regime has
really been a cultural success in this sense. The alternative explanation,
suggested by the case of Iraq, is the hypothesis of a “Republic of Fear,” to
use exile dissident writer Kanan Makiya’s term: a regime in which violence,
threats of violence, and enforced complicity in violence are overwhelming and
form the basis for the stability of the state. This is not a cultural normalcy but
a reign of terror. Following this line of thought with regard to Nazi Germany,
one can inquire into the character of the totalitarian state as a regime of
terror and angst, rather than as a merely distinctive cultural style.
Finally, if Saddam was like Hitler (and
obviously the point is not the assertion of absolute identity but a challenge
to consider similarities), then to what extent is the outside world’s response
to Saddam like the earlier response to Hitler? It is here that the discussion
of Saddam as Hitler overlaps with the question of anti-Americanism. The point
is not only to consider the intentional political allegory—we fought Hitler
therefore we must fight Saddam—but to remember how great the reluctance to
fight Hitler was. That historical appeasement mentality can help us understand
the contemporary reluctance to confront Saddam. The international response to
Hitler did not, after all, start in Normandy. There were long years of denial
and deferral.
Observers inside Germany and abroad minimized
Hitler’s importance in Weimar, and even after the Nazi accession to power in
1933, there was extensive acceptance, appeasement, and tolerance. Calls for
“regime change” were not common. Most egregious of course was the deep
resistance in “world opinion” to believing the accounts of mass murder. A
feature of modern world opinion is precisely this preference to avoid facing violence,
as well as the fascination with authoritarian leaders (consider the popularity
of dictators such as Stalin, Castro, and Mao in what are otherwise Western
democracies). The metaphor of Saddam and Hitler is therefore also an
opportunity to think through the psychology of this response to totalitarian leaders
and the states they command. Why is it easier to talk about instruments of
violence, the weapons of mass destruction, than to recognize victims of
violence? For parts of the public, the presence of weapons of mass destruction
was unquestionably more relevant than mass graves: a strange moral order,
indeed. Part of this dynamic has to do with the perverse consequence of a
defining feature of enlightened modernity, tolerance, which is strangely taken
to apply to criminal dictators too.
Respect for the sovereignty of states—and
their sovereigns— ranks well above any consideration of the well-being of citizens.
Hence also cultural relativism, which quickly defends a reign of terror as just
another way of life, for which we should show tolerance. The prewar political
debate is a case in point, with the extensive resistance, even among otherwise
human rights— oriented liberals, to discussions of regime change. This stance suggests
the defense of sovereignty as such, no matter what the character of the regime,
and therefore an inability to declare any regime unacceptable, which implies in
turn the obligatory acceptance of any regime, no matter how bad. It follows
that discussions of the domestic violence within another state are regarded
with apprehension and mistrust, no matter how great the human suffering. Here
the Saddam-as-Hitler metaphor takes another turn: the historical discounting of
the reports of Nazi death camps represented the same mentality as the
willingness to diminish the significance of Saddam’s campaign against the Kurds.
World opinion prefers to overlook genocide. Anti-Americanism results because
the United States challenged this moral lethargy.
In American political discourse, the metaphor
of Saddam as Hitler dates from the period following the Iraqi invasion of Kuwait
and referred at first solely to the phenomenon of international aggression.
Thus George H. W. Bush said in his August 8, 1990, address announcing the
deployment of U.S. forces to Saudi Arabia: “But if history teaches us anything,
it is that we must resist aggression or it will destroy our freedoms.
Appeasement does not work. As was the case in the 1930s, we see in Saddam
Hussein an aggressive dictator threatening his neighbors.” 1 In
the same vein, one week later, on August 15, Bush spoke at the Department of
Defense: “A half a century ago our nation and the world paid dearly for
appeasing an aggressor who should and could have been stopped.”2 It
was not difficult for the press to take the next step, name the dictator of the
1930s, and develop an analogy between Saddam and Hitler; but for official
discourse the matter involved only the fact of aggression and its corollary,
the historical lesson on the importance of refraining from policies of
appeasement.
Two months later, however, the presidential
account of his adversary changed significantly. In place of the fact of Iraqi aggression,
the focus shifted to the Iraqi leader, now associated with negative attributes
extending beyond the war of aggression. Perhaps this heightened rhetoric can be
attributed to the more sensational imagery used by the press, with which the president
or his speech writers had to compete; alternatively, the rhetorical shift may
reflect the fall election campaign and the political need to amplify public
interest through more pronounced statements. Surely part of the change,
however, must be explained realistically by the continuing brutality of the
Iraqi occupation and the only gradual recognition of this violence by the
outside world: it was no longer “just” a matter of the annexation of Kuwait by
an occupying army but of a reign of terror as well, which then compounded the
significance of the Hitler comparison. Thus in remarks at a fundraising
luncheon for the gubernatorial candidate Clayton Williams in Dallas on October 15,
1990, Bush asserted: “Hitler revisited. But remember, when Hitler’s war ended,
there were the Nuremberg trials.” The evil of the adversary goes hand in hand
with the expectation of a conclusive act of justice.
To substantiate the need for a trial,
however, Bush went into detail at a Republican campaign rally in Manchester,
New Hampshire, on October 23, 1990:
I am reading this great history of World War II. And I read the other
night just about how Hitler, unchallenged—the U.S. locked in its isolation in
those days, the late thirties—marched into Poland. Behind him—some of you will
remember this— came the Death’s Head regiments of the SS. Their role was to go
in and disassemble the country. Just as it happened in the past, the other day
in Kuwait, two young kids were passing out leaflets in opposition. They were
taken, their families made to watch, and they were shot to death—15-and
16-year-old. . . . We’re dealing with Hitler revisited, a totalitarianism and a
brutality that is naked and unprecedented in modern times. And that must not
stand.”3
Although the Hitler metaphor was used in an
effort to galvanize public opinion, its development over a two-month period
highlights the complex range of distinct issues at stake: aggression,
appeasement, violence against civilians, totalitarianism, and, in particular,
the personalization of the struggle with an eye to war crimes trials. The
latter point has to be seen not only as the rhetoric of the moment but as part
of the tradition, perhaps distinctively American, of focusing on the personal responsibility
of the adversary leader: Wilson’s insistence on the Kaiser’s culpability in the
First World War, for example, as well as the criminalization of enemy
leadership after the Second World War, both in Germany and in Japan.4 More
complexly and critically, one can suggest that the focus on the person of Saddam,
this individualization of history, derives from multiple sources: an
individualist ethos that looks for someone to blame as well as a mass-cultural
propensity to simplify complex matters in terms of individual celebrities—that
is, Saddam as Hitler, both as stars. Still, the focus on the individual,
Saddam, was not only a rhetorical effect, driven by the dynamic of political
discourse; it has to be seen primarily as a description of the priority of the
singular personality, the political leader, in the totalitarian state.
Before turning to the implications of this
personalization process, it is worth noting precisely what did not show up in the
public discourse, in the press, or in presidential addresses regarding the
similarities between Saddam and Hitler: multifold real historical ties between
National Socialism and the Ba’athist regime in Iraq, which had turned into
Saddam’s personal rule. An Iraqi-inflected pan-Arabism began to develop soon
after the end of the British mandate in 1932 and became the target of Nazi
foreign policy, given Germany’s strategic aspirations in Central Asia: the Nazi
youth leader Baldur von Schirach visited Baghdad in 1937, and the Futuwaa, a
youth league modeled on the Hitlerjugend, was soon established. Nazi Germany
(with Italy and, of course, the Soviet Union of the Hitler-Stalin Pact era)
supported the al-Rashid coup of 1941, including the “Farhud,” a pogrom against
Baghdad’s large Jewish population.5 The
coup was quickly suppressed, but it eventually became a mythic point of
reference for the later-established Ba’ath Party, which celebrated the coup as
“the first revolution for Arab liberation.”6
We know that a key Ba’athist ideologue,
Michel Aflaq, expressed admiration for Hitler, as did Saddam, and the Ba’athist
pursuit of power has elicited comparisons to Germany; thus Nicholas Natteau
wrote; “The street tactics of the Ba’ath against the ICP [Iraqi Communist
Party] or suspected ICP sympathizers resembled those of Hitler’s S.A. storm
troopers during the street battles of the late 1920s in Weimar Germany.”7 This
all suggests, however, that the Saddam-Hitler metaphor that emerged in response
to the occupation of Kuwait in 1990 touched, if only accidentally, on a longer
and more complex genealogical entwinement. The proximity of Saddam and Hitler
implied by the metaphor is, therefore, not just an abstract comparison of distinct
units but is grounded in the real history of Ba’ath ideology, Iraqi politics,
and Saddam’s personal admiration for Hitler as well as Stalin.8 It
is not just a matter of comparing Saddam to Hitler for contemporary political
reasons; there are also direct and multifaceted ideological connections.
Where culture mobilizes the masses, they are
probably following leaders. Totalitarian systems depend on the pairing of masses
and leaders. Mass culture implies, in one variant or another, a cult of
personality. Occasionally there are exceptions, when the utopias of free and
leaderless masses circulate: for example, in the thought of Rosa Luxemburg, of
the left-Communists whom Lenin famously denounced, or of some anarchists with
their cult of spontaneity. But these utopian movements are typically contained
and suppressed by more organizationally efficient institutions, and the masses
are eventually subordinated to a party and a leader. Both in Germany and Iraq,
the party overtook the people, and the leader came to eclipse the party.
The hypertrophic leader transforms the
standing of the “mass,” a term that
ceased to serve as a designation of the somehow really existing people and
became instead a politically charged category used to dominate and control.
Thus Aflaq’s 1979 celebration that “the role of the masses in the world has come
of age”9 was not about authentic popular culture: it meant instead
that the Iraqi population had been redefined as a compliant mass: the mass was
represented by the party, and the party was Saddam. In particular, Aflaq’s
assertion announced that the political adversary, the Iraqi Communist Party,
had been definitively defeated and with it the category of class: the age of
class struggle gave way to the age of the Arab mass. Yet Aflaq’s announcement
also pointed to the criminalization of any dissident or otherwise nonconformist
individuality, incompatible with the embracing and homogenizing category of
mass. To be individual would mean betraying the masses. This outcome is consistent
with the founding constitution of the Ba’ath party and its assertion that “all
existing differences between the members of the nation are superficial and
false, and will be dissipated within the anatomy of the Arab soul.”10 Individuality
and difference were proscribed. Pan-Arabism, at least in the version Aflaq bequeathed
to Iraqi Ba’athism, was not only about a transnational solidarity, vaguely
comparable to pan-Germanism (subtly shifting politics away from citizenship in
a nation-state to race, a pseudobiological category at odds with the notions of
citizenship) but also about the submission of the individual to the mass.
Pan-Arabism is ultimately one with the
enforced collectivism of Nazism as well as the left-modernist fascination with
liquidating individualism. Twentieth-century politicized mass culture, in its
several inflections, on the Right and on the Left, implies, tragically, a deep
hostility to individual subjectivity and privacy. The echoes of this
antisubjectivism reverberate through contemporary cultural theory (especially
in the shadow of poststructuralism), which may explain the scholarly reluctance
to address critically the illiberal regimes of totalitarian mass modernity.
The metaphor of Saddam and Hitler reappears
however in a very different context, when Iraqi exile writer and dissident Kanan
Makiya explores the character of Ba’athist politics by way of Hannah Arendt’s
study of totalitarianism, in particular with regard to the relationship of the
masses to the leader in regimes of mendacity. Thus the Saddam-as-Hitler
metaphor is not merely an artifact of George H. W. Bush’s war rhetoric; it also
serves the democratic Iraqi opposition in its efforts to make sense of the
Ba’ath catastrophe. Makiya’s interpretation of Iraq is refracted through
Arendt’s understanding of Nazi Germany.
In both Nazi Germany and Saddam’s Iraq,
“truth” is whatever the leader says, no matter how absurd or implausible and,
in fact, no matter how inconsistent or incompatible even with the leader’s own
earlier pronouncements. Thus Makiya, who is thinking about Iraq, cites Arendt,
who is commenting on Hitler and Stalin: “The totalitarian mass leaders based
their propaganda on the correct psychological assumption that . . . one could
make people believe the most fantastic statements one day, and trust that if
the next day they were given irrefutable proof of their falsehood, they would
take refuge in cynicism; instead of deserting the leaders who had lied to them,
they would protest that they had known all along that the statement was a lie
and would admire the leaders for their superior tactical cleverness.”11
Makiya’s point involves the character of the
loyalty that the masses bring to the regime. It is not a matter of a consensus
(i.e., the shared belief of a convinced public). It is not that the public somehow
accepts the propagandistic disinformation as representing a substantive truth
about which it might develop an informed opinion. Nor does the public succumb
to an imaginably effective cultural-industrial manipulation or some
restructured hegemony. All of these cultural-theoretical models fail. Instead,
Makiya claims that Iraqis largely recognize the falsehoods as false, which
instead of eliciting outrage leads to cynicism and even admiration for the
ability of the leader to change positions. Indeed it is not even a matter of
treating the statements of the regime as true—the expectation of a truthful
government is simply not a given—but only as performance, and it is through
performance, always more powerful than truth or rules, that Saddam acts out his
predominance: “. . . the Leader’s omnipotence is acted out dramatically, as
though performed on a stage. Favors are bestowed on people in such a way as to
break the very rules the Leader’s state enforces . . . ; his freedom to act,
even to break his own rules, is intentionally pitted against everyone else’s
profound unfreedom. The effect, however, is not to highlight the latter, but to
confound it with the former.”12 In a context of universal
falsehood, Iraqi society does not find sustenance in a successfully convincing
propaganda apparatus, some “mass culture” that elicits support and authentic
trust, but rather in the image of the great leader. Hero worship—that is, the
worship of one hero—is central to the regime, which authorizes no room for
disagreement or dissent. In other words, at stake is not an ideology of heroism
that might be taken to call on all individuals to excel and to act heroically but
rather a constant entwinement of the abjection of each individual, facing
constant admonitions to abjure all particularity, and the focus on the one
leader who is the collectivized nation. Saddam was Iraq in the sense of the
Nazi slogan Deutschland ist
Hitler.
It is worth observing Makiya follow Arendt in
one further step, as he highlights the freedom that was absent in Saddam’s Iraq.
Freedom—in the Ba’athist tradition—is only the freedom of the nation as a
whole, (i.e., a sort of decolonization as collectivism, and this is then
transferred onto the political leader).
There is no claim of individual freedom. Yet,
Makiya poignantly develops an alternative position: “The notion of freedom as a
political condition that only exists because of the capacity of human beings to
be different, to be in a minority, and not have to think the same deathly
‘free’ thoughts.” This version of freedom, he continues, “is absent in Iraqi
society. When it arose in the modern era, it was snuffed out, first by the
growing ideological hegemony of pan-Arabism and later by the social
organization of the second Ba’athist regime [i.e., post-1968]. The absence not
only of freedom but also of the very idea of this kind of freedom makes Saddam Husain’s
role-playing so effective.”13
Makiya’s claim regarding the political
freedom in the human condition translates Arendt’s political theory into Iraq. The
definition of freedom in terms of a human condition obviously stands at odds
with current academic dogma regarding essentialism and humanism; eventually the
political implications of this intellectual baggage may become clear. In the
context of this chapter, however, and the examination of the cross-national metaphor,
what resonates is the suggestion of an underdeveloped liberal tradition—a
standard piece of thinking about historical German political culture—but also a
nostalgia for a lost opportunity. Makiya suggests that between the
establishment of a parliamentary monarchy in 1932 and the seizure of power by the
Ba’ath Party in 1968, liberalizing possibilities in Iraq did in fact exist. The
Ba’ath, who suppressed that tradition of freedom, look back at the earlier era
with disdain, celebrating only the Nazi-supported 1941 coup. This historical
vision of the dictatorial party is analogous to the Nazi memory of the
Wilhelmine era and the Weimar “system,” both vilified as too liberal and too free.
Makiya’s underscoring of Saddam’s
performance—his drama and his role-playing—points to the prominence of the leader
as individual and as artist within the totalitarian system. Similarly, the
German author Thomas Mann once drew attention to aspects of Hitler’s
performance and its proximity to aspects of the artist.14 Saddam
and Hitler as artists? One might compare Hitler’s early interest in painting
with Saddam’s strange obsession with architecture.15 Yet
the point here is not the artistic production as such but rather the
performance of the political leader as itself the act of art. The great leader
of the masses stages himself as an artistic genius, precisely as part of his
political presence. Facing the degraded masses, the leader stands out and above
them as a unique individual, the creative genius: the artist. Saddam and Hitler
both projected themselves to the public as absolute and overriding, as two
examples can amply demonstrate.
While Hitler denigrates the conformist
masses, whom he regards as susceptible to propaganda, he heroizes great
individuals, to whom he attributes the artistic qualities of freedom and creativity.
Everyone else conforms and obeys, but the totalitarian leader as artist can
break all the rules (as in Makiya’s description of Saddam) while he asserts his
particular individuality against the world. Thus Hitler writes in Ralph
Manheim’s translation of Mein Kampf:
“Personality cannot be replaced; especially when it embodies not the mechanical
but the cultural and creative element. No more than a famous master can be
replaced and another take over the completion of the half-finished painting he
has left behind can the great poet and thinker, the great statesman and the
great soldier, be replaced. For their activity lies always in the province of
art. It is not mechanically trained, but inborn by God’s grace.”16 Different
legacies compete within those lines: the opposition of the mechanical and the
cultural, the cult of great masters, the priority of the aesthetic—all of these
might be taken as aspects of the shattered cultural tradition of the educated
middle class, the Bildungsbu¨rgertum.
Yet it is Hitler’s insistence on irreplaceability, a resistance to exchange,
that links his discourse to aspects of the aesthetic tradition: like the work
of art and the artist, the politician too is absolutely original and fully
unique. Where this claim becomes distinctively Hitler’s, however, and where it
stands absolutely at odds with Makiya’s Arendtian appeal to difference in the
human condition, is that—for Hitler—this uniqueness is the province of only a few,
the great, the masters.
The paragraphs that follow plunge,
characteristically, into Hitler’s antisemitism. The virtue of irreplaceability
does not apply to everyone. Yet Hitler does not exclude Jews alone. On the
contrary, he claims that most of humanity is barred from the realm of the
unique. Being genuinely individual is not part of the general human condition.
Uniqueness is, on the contrary, the exclusive privilege of the few. Meanwhile,
the many, the perpetually replaceable masses, depend on a few leaders, who are
alone distinct. Thus Hitler continues: “The greatest revolutionary changes and
achievements of this earth, its greatest cultural accomplishments, the immortal
deeds in the field of statesmanship, etc., are forever inseparably bound up
with a name and are represented by it. To renounce doing homage to a great
spirit means the loss of an immense strength which emanates from the names of
all great men and women.”17 Hence a vision in which the
few great creators tower over the conformist mass and demonstrate their
greatness through a distinctiveness that is—regardless of explicit field of
activity—fundamentally artistic.
This priority of leadership in the context of
mass society explains a characteristic aspect of Mein Kampf, the strange interspersion of autobiography
in the political program. Individual personality—Hitler’s memoir
writing—pervades the political polemic throughout the book. Indeed this is the
program announced in the preface to Mein Kampf, where Hitler states that the volume is
intended not only to describe “the aims of our movement” and its development
but also “to give an account of my own development.”18 There
is, however, a strange ambivalence about the project. Hitler concludes the
preface, to be sure, with a monumentalizing gesture: “for a doctrine to be
disseminated uniformly and coherently, its basic elements must be set down for
all time. To this end I wish to contribute these two volumes as foundation
stones in our common edifice.” Writing, he suggests, may guarantee eternal permanence
and preclude interpretive variance, despite the dissemination of the message.
Hence, the reassuring conclusion of the
preface: he is putting his message in stone to guarantee its immutability. Yet
this follows immediately on the unintentional expression of an underlying doubt
about the book: “I know that men are won over less by the written than by the
spoken word, that every great movement on this earth owes its growth to great
orators and not to great writers.” Hitler the orator seems to doubt Hitler the
writer. Or is it the pervasive suspicion of writing, literature, and the press that
leads Hitler to this paean to orality? The heavy edifice he constructs in Mein Kampf recalls
the Landsberg prison in which he wrote the book, but the closing of the preface
also takes on an epitaphic character: a conclusiveness, an end, which would only
be mitigated by live oration.
The preface to Mein Kampf sheds light on the cultural character of
totalitarianism with its tension between between writing and oration and
between permanence and vitality. This conflict is symptomatic of the
totalitarian condition: the leader is at the center of the movement, but the
cumbersome apparatus of the movement (the party and its bureaucracy) may come
to be at odds with the principle of leadership, which requires the possibility of
constant redefinition. The need to write, in order to build an edifice,
conflicts with the need never to be held to one’s word since truth is only
contingent, whereas writing is permanent. Orality provides a flexibility that
literacy, with its inherently critical potential, undermines through its
durability. As creative artist, the leader can always say something new, with little
concern for consistency. It is this absolute elevation of the leader that is
symptomatic.
Saddam Hussein imitated this elevation of the
totalitarian leader that had been prefigured by Hitler and Stalin. In Mein Kampf,
Hitler’s autobiography intrudes into the political agenda. The Iraqi corollary,
with a similar magnification of the leader, is the infamous Victory Arch in
Baghdad. It is a grotesque monument, completed in August 1988 to celebrate the
(dubious) victory over Iran, and unveiled in the midst of the genocidal anfal campaign against the Kurds.
Saddam designed the monument himself, intending it as an Iraqi competitor to
the Parisian Arc de Triomphe, but Saddam is present in the monument in a way that
goes far beyond his having envisioned it. Just as Hitler, the individual,
protrudes into the Nazi program of Mein Kampf, so
too does Saddam, the person, dominate the Iraqi national monument.
Makiya describes the monument as follows: Two
steel forearms “come bursting out of the ground like bronze tree trunks and
rise holding a sixty-six-foot-long sword in each fist. The two swords cross to
form the apex of the arch at a point roughly 130 feet above the ground. Each
forearm and fist, with the steel frame on which it is fixed, weighs 40 tons.
Each sword, made of stainless steel, weighs 24 tons. This steel . . . was made
by melting down the actual weapons of Iraqi ‘martyrs.’ War debris in the shape
of 5,000 real Iranian helmets, taken from the battlefield, are gathered up in
two nets (2,500 helmets per net).
. . . To look at the helmets in the knowledge
that their scratches, dents, and bullet holes are real, that human heads might
well have exploded inside them, is . . . breathtaking.”19 Indeed,
it is almost as breathtaking as the one defining characteristic of the monument,
the bizarre fact that the two forearms are not sculpted objects but castings
taken from plaster casts of Saddam’s own arms and then enlarged. In 1991, still
compelled to write under the pseudonym Samir al-Khalil, Makiya pondered this
point: why a casting, which preserves all the imperfections, the scars, the veins,
and the hair follicles of the forearms, rather than a sculpture that might have
idealized the body parts? His answer: “Only casting renders absolute authority
(which is singular and abstract, yet experienced in all the minutiae of daily life
in Iraq) visible and corporeal, while retaining the aura of absolute
uniqueness, so essential to the work of art even in this age of mechanical
reproduction.”20
The projection of the leader’s irreducible
uniqueness into the artistic edifice, in homology to Mein Kampf,
displays the absolute priority of personal power. It is not some idea or the spirit
of the nation that pervades this war memorial. It is the unquestionable
authority of the lord and master, the totalitarian leader. The masses are
instrumentalized, literally—they are made identical with their instruments of
violence—in the swords made from the weapons of the Iraqi soldiers, or they are
degraded in the display of the Iranian helmets (degraded and desecrated:
elsewhere Makiya reports how the corpses of the victims executed by Saddam’s
police were denied ritual cleaning, thus preventing their entry into paradise).
The infinite narcissism of the leader means that nothing else counts, reality dwindles
away, and the world can be annihilated. As different as these two entities are,
Mein Kampf and
the Victory Arch, both demonstrate the same imperious standing of the leader.
In terms of political self-presentation, the metaphor—Saddam as Hitler— surely
holds.
Saddam and Hitler: it is not difficult to
ascribe to each a cultural penumbra, the writers, artists, and intellectuals
who, sometimes bought, sometimes in voluntary delusion, pursued an affiliation
with the totalitarian regime: Riefenstahl, Speer, Heidegger, Nolde, or the
various Arab writers and Western architects who have benefited from Baghdad’s
largesse.21 In this context, one can cite as well the cultural
programs of the regimes, the celebration of particular traditions or the
symbolladen construction projects: Saddam chose to rebuild Babylon. He would
often stage himself as the heir to ancient civilizations, receiving the law
from Hammurabi, using bricks, on each of which his name was imprinted: the
intrusion of the leader into monumentality, as much an act of possession and
naming as Hitler’s placing himself in the center of Mein Kampf.22
Did this sort of culture really matter? It
remains an open question whether this cultural frenzy—writers’ congresses, architectural
competitions, museum exhibitions—played any significant role in generating
support for the regime, as measured against the primary feature of life in the
totalitarian state: fear of violence, including the moral degradation
associated with complicity in violence. The contempt that the German author
Ernst Ju¨nger, referring to battlefield experience in the First World War,
could feel toward the aestheticizing world of bourgeois security can shed light
on the tendency to treat the totalitarian regime as an aesthetic style. In
Ju¨nger’s words: “Our blood is full of passions and feelings, that have no
place at teatime.” 23 Or more explicitly
anticultural: “This is not the time to read Werther with a tearful eye.”24 The
existential reality of the battle stands at odds with the sentimentalism that
Ju¨nger associates with Goethe’s novel The Sorrows of Werther. War, so Ju¨nger implies,
has no space for culture.
It is a time of violence, not of art. This
implies, however, that the culture of the totalitarian regime—if “culture” is
the right word at all—is not primarily its aesthetic works but the ubiquity of
violence and fear. In this view, the Nazi regime was defined less by its
various propagandistic art exhibits than by its brutality and murder, public
and private. This is surely true of Iraq. Despite the elaboration of a Ba’athist
ideology, with influences from Sorel (through Aflaq) and Fichte (through
Husri),25 it is not the credibility of that confused amalgam
of intellectual history that held Saddam’s Iraq together but rather fear.
Khidir Hamza, a key defector from the Iraqi nuclear program, writes of viewing
a film of a “party denunciation meeting” in which the members of the party
elite were forced to shoot each other.26
Makiya similarly describes the double
strategy of public and private violence: the public hanging of Jews accused of
espionage in January 1969, at the outset of the regime, attended by thousands;
and the private torture, that concluded with sealed coffins to keep the bodies
invisible. “Fear is the cement that holds together this strange body politic in
Iraq,” writes Makiya: not ideology, loyalty, or even tradition. “The public is
atomized and broken up, which is why it can be made to believe anything.” Mass
society in the totalitarian world is, in effect, not a mass at all, but the
ruins of the former civil society and communities. Makiya continues: “A society
that used to revel in politics is not only subdued and silent, but profoundly
transformed. Fear is the agency of that transformation; the kind of fear that comes
not only from what the neighbors might say, but that makes people careful of
what they say in front of their children. This fear has become a part of the
psychological constitution of citizenship.”27
It is a terroristic society, and the
description holds as much for Saddam’s Iraq as it did for Hitler’s Germany:
cultures of fear, rather than art. Terror and the shame of complicity define
individual lives. For example, for those Germans who viewed the boycott of
Jewish stores in April 1933, enforced by Nazi paramilitary gangs, fear of
facing similar threats and the shame of having stood by passively surely must
have left traces that determined their subsequent relationship to the regime: a
relationship of degradation and humiliation rather than of voluntary
participation or ideological consensus. More important than the mobilized
culture portrayed in Leni Riefenstahl’s films, the Nazi reign of terror was
defined by an immobilized conscience. It is here that the German author Hans
Magnus Enzensberger’s February 1991 reflection on Saddam and Hitler (“Hitler’s Successor:
Saddam Hussein in the Context of German History”) becomes pertinent.
Enzensberger argues that in contrast to the standard dictators of the twentieth
century, who were eager to enrich themselves and therefore calculable, Hitler
and Saddam represent something different, a desire for destruction as such.
Plausible goals or a serious ideology are
absent. Rather than personal gain or principled ideals, their ultimate goal is
annihilation, a deep death wish, from which their own people, indeed the leader
himself, is not excepted. In Iraq and Germany, this annihilationist leadership
could succeed because of the widespread feelings of national humiliation—the
defeat in the First World War, the legacy of colonialism—and these instincts
were then available for manipulation by the unlimited will to death of the
totalitarian political leader. Thus Enzensberger concludes: “The enemy of
humanity can arm himself with the combined death energy of the masses, which
gives him power bordering on genius: the infallible sense for unconscious
stirrings in his followers. He does not operate with arguments but with
emotions that unhinge any form of logic.”28
Enzensberger’s account is at odds with
Makiya’s, particularly with regard to the description of the population: in Makiya’s
“republic of fear,” the bulk of the population is terrorized and terrified. In
contrast, Enzensberger sketches a fanatic and fanatically loyal population. The
distinction is significant, but in both models the center of social life is destruction:
the threat of destruction directed by the state toward the population— as well
as toward external enemies—or the self-destructive vengeance attributed to the
population in pursuit of a death that it desires. The experience in postwar
Iraq confirms both visions. There is evidence that the bulk of Iraqis
appreciate the end of Saddam’s reign of terror, but there is also a hard core
of “dead-enders,” blindly loyal to the
leader and indifferent to the prospect of continued hardship for the Iraqi people.
Was there a totalitarian “culture” that was
more than the fear that terrorized and atomized individuals felt? Enzensberger
at least suggests that there was a kind of mobilized culture in the totalitarian
state, but it was a mobilization directed not toward an imaginable victory but
only toward devastation. Nazi architecture, understood in this sense, should
not be thought of as best exemplified by the massive megalomania of Albert
Speer’s building plans but by the real-world leveling of European cities, the
genuine goal of the Nazi imagination. In fact the same implies for the Allied
destruction of German cities, an architecture of ruins, which, in
Enzensberger’s account, was somehow not the result of the Nazi military
failings but the very goal of the Nazis from the start. The Nazis pursued total
war as they sang, “until everything falls to pieces.” Their goal was to
transform the Volk ohne Raum—“people
without space,” the title of a pro-Nazi novel advocating German
colonialism—into pure Raum ohne Volk,
space without people, where human life has come to an end. It was American and
English bombs that leveled German cities, but that destruction was the result
of a death wish deeply embedded in the Nazi imagination from the start.
Saddam’s murders never numbered as high as the mass murder under Hitler or
Stalin, but a similar process pertained: the program for mass destruction was
directed against his own people as much as against external enemies.
If the metaphor holds and Saddam is like
Hitler, then how the world responded to Nazi Germany sheds light on how it has responded
to Iraq. Of course, the analogy is not perfect, and the historical
circumstances were different, nonetheless there is one striking similarity. In
neither case did the egregious violence of the totalitarian regime lead
directly to unanimous protests and opposition. On the contrary, in both cases
the serious military engagement—the war against Nazi Germany and the war against
Saddam’s Iraq—took place only after extensive equivocation and denial. A desire
to ignore violence prevailed, and that inclination grew stronger, the more
terrible the violence. As far as Iraq is concerned, the question of compliance
with U.N. disarmament mandates was long given pride of place and was split—in
the interest of respecting state sovereignty, no matter how miserable the
character of the state—from questions of the treatment of the domestic
population, about which a grotesque and chilling silence prevailed. Even after
the war, the mass graves simply count less than a determination about the
weapons of mass destruction. We would rather not hear. The secret of domestic
violence, in Iraq or elsewhere, is not easily addressed; indeed it is
preferably ignored.
While the initial German lesson cited by
George H. W. Bush in 1990 was the admonition against appeasing an international
aggressor, there is surely another lesson as well: the urgency to refuse to
accept the world’s predisposition to remain impervious to genocide and terror.
What is the iron law that makes world opinion—the editorial pages of leading
newspapers, the U.N. committees, and the experts of the public sphere—so
predisposed to ignore the news of violence, and are we condemned to obey this
law? Surely the victims of violence want their story to be heard. For example,
Makiya concludes an interview with Taimour, a young Kurd who, as a
twelve-year-old, witnessed the mass destruction of his village and the killing
of his family:
“If you could choose, what would
you want to do in your life now?
I don’t know for myself.
Is there something you want out of life very much?”
Yes.
What?
To be a known person.
A known person?
Yes.
Known for what?
The Anfal.
Do you want to be known more for the Anfal or for being
a peshmerga?
For Anfal.
What do you mean ‘known for Anfal ’?
I want the world to know what happened to me.”29
The problem is, however, that much of the
world does not want to know. The desire to be untroubled by other’s suffering is
often greater than the sense of human compassion. The similarity of Nazi
Germany and Saddam’s Iraq is confirmed by the comparable avoidance strategies
that outsiders employed in order to ignore. The severe violence of the
totalitarian regime elicits nothing more readily than silence among the
well-meaning carriers of world opinion: mass murder often provokes less protest
than a trivial scandal in a run-of-the-mill city hall. As Enzensberger put it,
“Then, as now, the world did not want to come to terms with what it confronted.
Foreign governments regarded Hitler as a statesman representing ‘legitimate
concerns,’ whom one had to accommodate, with whom one had to negotiate. The
winners of WWI welcomed him as an ‘agent of stability,’ as a trading partner,
as a counterweight to the Soviet threat; in other words, one dealt with him on
a normal political level and trusted that it was a matter of solving conflicts
of interest.”30
The flight into normalcy was not merely a
matter of selfinterest but also, indeed above all, a denial of the horror, a refusal
to hear the news of the death camps, just as today Saddam’s genocide is not
given serious consideration, especially by opponents of the war. This is as
true in the Arab world as in the democratic West: the man responsible for
killing the most Muslims in history does not face much retrospective criticism
among Arab leaders. Thus Mohamad Jasem al-Sager, the head of the Foreign
Affairs Committee in the Kuwaiti People’s Council, commented bitterly on Arab
parliamentarians’ silence regarding the evidence of mass killings under Saddam:
“Is it possible that the representatives of the Arab nations refuse to abide by
even the most basic duties of their profession—representing their people? Is it
possible that they fail to utter a single word of sympathy for the thousands of
victims of the Arab dictator? . . . Arab parliamentarians limit their
condemnation to the Zionists and the foreign invasion and have purposefully
forgotten the crimes committed under our noses. Would these Arab
parliamentarians dare to hold the gaze of an Iraqi woman sitting at the grave
of her murdered children? We have seen thousands of people gathering the
remains of their relatives in plastic bags.”31
Perhaps Arab parliamentarians have
ideological grounds to avoid criticizing another Arab leader: a misguided
ideology to be sure. Yet there was hardly a comparable rationale in the West for
politicians and demonstrators to come to the defense of the Iraqi regime—except
the cowardly rationale of avoiding addressing the violence. In the end, it was
left to the United States to respond to the fact of Saddam’s genocide. George
W. Bush called it “evil” and scandalized those segments of the
cultural-relativist public who would have preferred to ignore it.
Anti-Americanism derives from many sources,
as we have seen in the previous chapters, but among these sources one figures quite
large: the high moral standard that the United States has set, in the Iraq war
and in fact since the Nuremberg Trials, with regard to Nazi Germany. Whether
the United States has always lived up to these principles is another matter,
but historical failings never disprove the validity of ideals. The United
States has played an indispensable role in the wars against totalitarian
violence and has thereby raised moral standards in world affairs. The United
States has disrupted the blissful ignorance of a world opinion prepared to
ignore suffering. Resentment results. Anti-Americanism is the expression of a
desire to avoid the moral order and to withhold compassion from the victims of violence.
1. George H. W. Bush, “Address to the Nation Announcing the Deployment
of United States Armed Forces to Saudi Arabia,” August 8, 1990, http://
bushlibrary.tamu.edu.
2. George H. W. Bush, “Remarks to Department of Defense Employees,” August
15, 1990, http://bushlibrary.tamu.edu.
3. George H. W. Bush, “Remarks at a Republican Campaign Rally in
Manchester, New Hampshire,” October 23, 1990, http://bushlibrary.tamu.edu.
4. Cf. Daniel Moran, “Restraints on Violence and the Reconstruction of
International Order after 1945,” in War and Terror,
ed. Frank Trommler and Michael Geyer, Vol. 14 (Washington: American Institute
for Contemporary German Studies Humanities Series, forthcoming).
5. Majid Khadduri, Independent: A
Study in Iraqi Politics (London: Oxford University Press, 1960),
172–73.
6. Kanan Makiya, Republic of
Fear (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1998), 151.
7. Nicholas Natteau, Saddam over
Iraq—How Much Longer? A Study of the Ba’thist Destruction of Iraqi Civil Society
and the Prospects for Its Rebirth (master’s thesis, Boston
University, 1997), www.joric.com/Saddam/Saddam.htm.
8. “The lessons of 1963 had taught him that destroying civil society was
not enough to ensure the IBP’s [Iraqi Ba’th Party’s] stay in power. Like
Hitler, he now understood that this goal would require Ba’thizing not just the
government, but the state, the military, and ultimately every nook and cranny
of society. With this goal in mind, he was particularly attracted to the
organizational methods used by Hitler to Nazify Germany. He understood that to
ensure the party’s complete domination over Iraq, society had to be regimented
into the new Ba’thist order. According to one British journalist who visited
Iraq in 1975, a government translator confided to him that Saddam Hussein’s
half-brother-inlaw and head of intelligence, Barzan al-Tikriti, had asked him
to procure books on Nazi Germany: ‘He believed that Saddam himself was
interested in this subject, not for any reason to do with racism or anti-semitism,
. . . but as an example of the successful organization of an entire society by
the state for the achievement of national goals.’” Efraim Karsh and Inari
Rautsi, Saddam Hussein: A Political Biography (New
York, Toronto: The Free Press, 1991), 89. Cited by Natteau, Saddam over Iraq.
9. Makiya, Republic of Fear,
243.
10. Ibid., 197.
11. Ibid., 115.
12. Ibid., 116.
13. Ibid., 116. Makiya consistently spells the name of the Iraqi
dictator in this manner.
14. Thomas Mann, “Bruder Hitler” (1938), in Essays,
Vol. 4, Achtung, Europa! 1933–1938 (Frankfurt
am Main: S. Fischer, 1995), 305–12.
15. Cf. Said K. Aburish, Saddam Hussein:
The Politics of Revenge (London: Bloomsbury, 2000), 265–66.
16. Adolf Hitler, Mein Kampf,
trans. Ralph Manheim (London: Hutchinson, 1969), 320.
17. Ibid.
18. Ibid., xlv.
19. Kanan Makiya, Cruelty and
Silence: War, Tyranny, Uprising, and the Arab World (New
York: Norton, 1994), 209.
20. Samir al-Khalil (Kanan Makiya), The Monument:
Art, Vulgarity, and Responsibility in Iraq (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1991), 6.
21. Cruelty and Silence provides
extensive discussion of how the Iraqi regime bought off Arab intellectuals to
silence criticism and gain a public relations advantage.
22. Cf. Neil MacFaquhar, “Hussein’s Babylon: A Beloved Atrocity,” New York Times, August 19, 2003, A10.
23. Ernst Ju¨nger, “Der Kampf als inneres Erlebnis,” in Sa¨mtliche Werke Essays I: Betrachtungen zur Zeit 7.1
(Stuttgart: Klett Verlag, 1980), 95.
24. Ibid., 39.
25. Cf. Makiya, Republic of
Fear, 152.
26. Khidir Hamza, Saddam’s
Bombmaker: The Terrifying Story of the Iraqi Nuclear and Biological Weapons
Agenda (New York: Scribner, 2000), 112–15.
27. Makiya, Republic of
Fear, 275.
28. Hans Magnus Enzensberger, “Hitler’s Successor: Saddam Hussein in the
Context of German History,” Telos 86
(Winter 1990–91), 156.
29. Makiya, Cruelty and
Silence, 199.
30. Enzensberger, “Hitler’s Successor,” 157.
31. MEMRI, Special Dispatch Series,
no. 533, July 2, 2003, http://memri.org/ bin/articles.cgi?Page_archives&Area_sd&ID_SP53303.
==============================
Earlier
chapters have traced the cultural and ideological character of
anti-Americanism: how it acts like an obsession or prejudice, impervious to
facts, and how it derives from deepseated European anxieties about the “new
world” and the promise it bears for democracy and capitalism. In addition,
chapter 4 has shown how anti-Americanism burgeoned in the context of the Iraq
war, the experience of which was colored by the memories of twentieth-century
totalitarianism. In this chapter, we turn to a different inflection of
anti-Americanism. Anti-Americanism is certainly not the same as the movement
against globalization; indeed there are American opponents of globalization—as
free trade—who are hardly anti-American in their cultural and political views.
Nonetheless, there is a large overlap between antiglobalization and
anti-Americanism, which this chapter explores.
In
standard usage, the term “globalization” refers to the economic process of
increased international trade and investment associated with a long-term
decline in the cost of transportation and communication. The accelerated
mobility of both capital and labor ensues, generating the flow of goods,
services, and people across national-political boundaries. This international character
of economic activity is hardly new; there is a long prehistory to international
trade and long-distance migration. The spread of economic relations across the
borders of states has been under way for centuries.
However,
objective measurements are just one side of the story; subjective experience is
another. Whether one sees globalization as a long-term feature of economic life
or as a largely recent phenomenon, it is clear that the public discussion of globalization
and, more precisely, the protest movement against globalization emerged
suddenly during the 1990s, and this antiglobalization movement continues to
resonate in many quarters around the world. (There is some irony in the fact
that antiglobalization spread rapidly and with ease across international borders,
exemplifying a certain cultural globalization: there is nothing more globalized
than the opposition to globalization.) Given the articulation of
antiglobalization sentiment in diverse contexts, it is not surprising that
political motivations and sentiments are not uniform or homogenous. Hostility
to globalization is driven by distinct interests and arguments in different
locations: opposing McDonald’s franchises in France is not necessarily cut from
the same cloth as opposing free trade in developing countries. Nonetheless,
there is a shared idiom of protest against globalization that characterizes a
subculture from Berlin to Berkeley. At its center is an economic claim.
Although
most professional economists see free trade and antiprotectionism as
preconditions for the production of wealth and overcoming poverty, the critics
of globalization typically reject this neoliberalism and call in various, if
often vague, ways for regimes of increased protectionism and regulation. On one
level, the critique of globalization is therefore about the appeal for increased
political intervention in economic processes. Indeed, the critique of globalization
has become the predominant form of anticapitalism in the post-Communist era. Antiglobalization
is not only about a protest against transnational processes; it is also about a
positive advocacy for expanded political restrictions on the economy. The
collapse of the Soviet Union and its satellite states marked the conclusion of
a history of an economic idea, the ideal of the planned economy associated with
Communism since 1917; the remaining power of Communist parties in China, North
Korea, Vietnam, and Cuba clearly has nothing more than a residual character. Communism
certainly no longer projects a world-revolutionary project, as was once the
case in the heyday of Russian prominence. Yet while the Communist critique of
capitalism has essentially ceased to command any serious attention, the
critiques of globalization have taken its place, continuing the attack on the
market economy, typically with no reflection on the historical failure of the
communist enterprise. It is therefore more than a coincidence that
antiglobalization became a popular ideology only once the bipolar world of the
cold war came to a definitive end: it has filled the space that Communism
vacated.
Antiglobalization,
as post-Communist anticapitalism, restages the antagonism between political and
economics actors (i.e., between the state and the market, reflecting
alternative orientations toward geographic space). The components of
globalization, especially more cost-efficient transportation and communication,
involve capabilities to reduce the relative importance of spatial location. The
global economy is therefore marked by the heightened mobility of goods,
information, wealth, and labor. In contrast, political power is classically
sedentary. It has traditionally been exercised through particular political
units (i.e., states), which are defined in territorial terms. This spatiality
of political power is not only a modern phenomenon; on the contrary, it
reflects the nature of power and force in the human condition altogether.
However, the priority of territorial identity took on an amplified importance
in the modern age with its emphasis on the nation-state and the derivation of sovereignty
from the people as defined in residential terms.
Democracy
derives its legitimacy from the will of the people inhabiting an area ruled by
the state. This spatialization of political power stands at odds with the
transgressive mobility associated with trade, in particular, and globalization
more broadly. The critique of globalization therefore involves an effort to
reassert the primacy of territory over exchange and of the state over economy.
The formula is surely not the same as the erstwhile communist model of the
nationalization of private property, but it does imply homologous efforts to
maintain and strengthen regimes of regulation, as opposed to deregulation, and
therefore to restrict aspects of free trade. Antiglobalization advocates the reassertion
of the power of the state against the freedom of the market.
Yet
this characterization of antiglobalization as the post-Communist form of
anticapitalism only catches one dimension, the debate over economic policies,
which is frequently overshadowed by other more subjective and affectively
charged issues. In other words, the discourse of antiglobalization is arguably less
the consequence of the acceleration of international trade and more the product
of certain political, rather than economic, shifts. For what is at stake is not
only the collapse of communism as an economic paradigm but the corollary emergence
of the United States as the one political and military superpower. The rise of
American power of course began much earlier, at the latest in the era of the
First World War, but its significance only became fully clear with the end of
the cold war and the disappearance of any credible challenge to American primacy.
Antiglobalization, strictly speaking, may entail an economic protest (no matter
how dubious the economics) against capitalism, but in practice, it is
inseparable from hostility to the spread of American political influence as
well.
In
many instances, anticapitalism and anti-Americanism are indistinguishable in
the discourse of antiglobalization, except that anti-Americanism typically
includes hostility to American foreign policy and cultural influence that may
not be directly associated with economic matters, narrowly defined. The
economic critique of globalization is heuristically separable from other
elements; in practice, the economic campaign against inadequate labor
conditions in third world factories is closely intertwined with ecological
advocacy for the Kyoto Treaty, human-rights concerns about indigenous peoples,
feminist support for women’s rights, and the legalistic expansion of
institutions of international governance (such as the International Criminal
Court). In this diverse and multi-issue field of international protest, in
which anticapitalism and anti-Americanism overlap, many ideological components
play important roles.
Of
particular concern is a disproportionate focus on Israel and Palestine,
accorded attention far beyond that given other local conflicts (e.g., Chechnya,
Kashmir, Kurdistan, or Tibet). Anticapitalism has always carried some messy
intellectual baggage, including a predisposition to associate capitalism and Judaism.
In the context of American support for Israel, a virulent strand of
antisemitism has developed that further complicates the antiglobalization
discourse. Antiglobalization, in other words, is embedded in a strange
political culture that combines anti-Americanism, anticapitalism, and
antisemitism, along with a generalized resistance to modernity and the free
market.
In
order to understand this potent mix of ideological currents, it is helpful to
look at two key intellectual and literary exponents of this diffuse development.
Neither the French sociologist Jean Baudrillard nor the Indian author Arundhati
Roy is, strictly speaking, a leader of the antiglobalization movement (although
Roy in fact is quite engaged as an activist opposing large dam-building
projects in India). For our purposes here, the key is not their specific
positions on particular political issues but rather the larger worldview that
they convey and its symptomatic standing for the nature of antiglobalization,
as it overlaps with anti-Americanism.
The
philosophical agenda of antiglobalization involves the defense of multiplicity
as against domination by a uniform power, of plurality as against singularity.
The movement itself has a pluralistic appearance. Antiglobalization involves
advocacy for multiple issues, each with its own legitimacy, local significance,
and moral standing. Yet in fact this diversity of positions quickly succumbs to
the process of homogenization: antiglobalization rapidly imposes a global
logic, a uniform onesize-fits-all argument, onto the multiplicity of different
claims.
In
other words, the protest movement ends up reproducing the same totalizing logic
that it has projected onto its adversary. The result is the paranoid vision of
a totalizing opponent—the notion that American power is so great that it is
responsible for any mishap in the world—as well as a predisposition toward the internal
repression of difference, ambiguity, and debate. The antiglobalization movement
is not the Communist Party, but there is little room to deviate from the
accepted “line.”
This
implosion, by which antiglobalization globalizes itself, can be traced
particularly clearly in the writings of the French philosopher and social theorist
Jean Baudrillard, especially in his generalized account (written after the
September 11 attacks) of a battle between singularity and particularity. For
Baudrillard, globalization means not only the international expansion of the market
but also the spread of the universe of symbols: a merely economic protectionism
is therefore hopelessly inadequate against what he designates as semiotic
promiscuity. “In cultural terms, it is the promiscuity of all signs and values,
in other words, pornography. Because the global diffusion of anything through
the network amounts to promiscuity, there is no need for sexual obscenity.”1 The
resistance to this symbolic exchange takes on diverse, indeed antagonistic
forms; in this sense, Baudrillard recognizes the internal multiplicity of
antiglobalization.2 Yet quickly all resistance
is defined as a hostility to the same enemy, and the internal process of
homogenization ensues. It becomes the conformism of the nonconformists.
It
was, for Baudrillard, September 11 that concretized this inversion: a single,
all-encompassing, global logic took over the vision of antiglobalization. The
protest movement against uniformity succumbed to its own negative vision.
Suddenly, all local strategies of terrorism, with their specific causes and
goals, were seen as culminating in the same, all-defining act of terrorism. For
Baudrillard, “Terrorism is an act that restores an irreducible particularity in
the middle of a generalized exchange system. All particularities (species,
individuals, cultures) which today challenge the establishment of global
circulation directed by one single power take their revenge and their death
through this terrorist transformation of the situation.”3 Not
only does Baudrillard—like other European intellectuals discussed in chapter
2—thereby provide an explicit defense of terrorism. He also subsumes all local
practices of resistance into the unifying logic of the one grand terrorist
deed. The movement that began as the advocacy of difference against the empire
of sameness ends up imposing its own sameness on all its components.
One
intriguing implication of Baudrillard’s claim—that all local resistance to
globalization was already inherent in the September 11 attacks—is that the
allegedly extensive international expressions of solidarity in the immediate
aftermath of the attacks, the protestations of compassion and identification
with the United States, may have been less than sincere, perhaps even only
superficial and perfunctory. The discussion of public opinion data in chapter 1
corroborates this claim. One can conclude that the turn of European opinion
against the United States in the subsequent year, particularly in regard to the
Iraq war, had less to do with the alleged diplomatic failures of the Bush administration
than with an ambiguity inherent in those initial expressions of sympathy, which
were never very far from the accusation that the attacks were actually
deserved. For our purposes here, however, what is more important than the slide
in European public opinion is the question of how antiglobalization globalizes
itself into a single logic, undermining its original multiplicity.
A
single world power is cast in an apocalyptic struggle with a singularized
opposition: two omnipresent agents in a Manichean paranoia. There is no longer
any particularity that stands outside the all-consuming global antagonism, and
consequently, no individuality either. The anxiety of the government security apparatus
that terrorists may lurk anywhere is actually quite moderate when contrasted
with the mentality of the protest movement, the persecution complex of the
globalization-critics. They rigorously ascribe all evil to the United States
and its capitalism: nothing is beyond American power, nothing beyond American
control, no misfortune for which American capitalism is not guilty.
Meanwhile,
the critics of globalization claim for themselves the moral superiority derived
from the position of underdevelopment: their de facto celebration of
backwardness is taken as the foundation for a critique of civilization. The
contrast with all ideologies of progress, even including classical Marxism, is quite
clear. For Marxists, backwardness only meant poverty; for the opponents of
globalization, backwardness is imagined to be the guarantor of genuine
intelligence and ethical judgment. Ultimately, this represents a late version
of the romantic fascination with “the noble savage.” Baudrillard casts this
superior primitive as a terrorist, while Roy, as we will see, ends up in the celebration
of indigenous culture and hostility to the West.
For
Baudrillard, antiglobalization, including terrorism, is the result of
globalized modernity, not in the obvious sense that globalization may provoke
resistance among its victims but in the sense that the totalizing system itself
yearns for its own destruction. Terrorism is not, he argues, the result of some
exterior force that opposes modernization but “the verdict and the sentence
that this society directs at itself.”4 This
claim is fully consistent with Baudrillard’s more extreme formulation with regard
to September 11 that there is “a terrorist imagination in all of us. . . .
Basically, they did it, but we wanted it.”5 In
both cases, his argument involves claiming that antiglobalization, even in its
most destructive form, does not come from the outside but expresses the
self-destructive desire of modernity itself.
As a
theoretician of antiglobalization, however, what he demonstrates in fact is the
opposite: the manner in which diverse cultural positions or singularities
dissolve into a generalized movement driven by the paranoid vision of an
undifferentiated and inescapable market. In other words, the pathological
projection is not, as Baudrillard claims, the result of modernity but rather,
the characteristic perspective of the critics of globalization, who fantasize
conspiracies and contamination everywhere.
Capitalism
becomes the pandemic against which local virtue must protect itself by
resisting promiscuity. Baudrillard’s identification of this anxiety regarding
semiotic contamination is useful in explaining the moment of sexual repression
in antiglobalization— the reluctance to criticize the Taliban is evidence on
this point—and betrays the repressive and xenophobic predisposition in the
movement, the fear of contact with the foreign. This outcome is particularly
clear in the next example.
Baudrillard
himself typically maintains a scholarly and sociological distance from his
material. Even while attacking the homogenizing power of global capitalism, in
a way that is clearly directed against the United States, his anti-Americanism remains
muffled and camouflaged by the conventions and forms of a generalizing and
abstract social theory. His essays represent the cool end of the spectrum of
the rhetorical registers of antiglobalization.
The
writings of Arundhati Roy present a strikingly different model. To be sure,
Roy’s account resembles Baudrillard’s to the extent that both elaborate a
worldview that links an antidevelopmental cult of backwardness to strident
antiglobalization: maintaining the local becomes a universal program. Yet Roy displays
none of Baudrillard’s conceptual abstraction and objective tone. Instead of
scholarly distance, her critique of globalization grows shrill, and her
anti-Americanism takes on an urgent ring. For this reason, the essays she has
written as a public intellectual have been criticized for the lack of serious
substance, and the political effect of her role in protest movements has been
subject to skeptical scrutiny. Nonetheless, the character of her
discourse—rather than the substance of her claims and arguments—is of interest
in this context, since it illuminates some features of the affect and
projections associated with antiglobalization. Why does anti-Americanism as
antiglobalization sometimes sound fanatic?
Roy
earned international acclaim with her novel The God of Small Things, which won the Booker
Prize in 1997. (A critic of globalization, she nonetheless belongs to the
growing group of celebrity authors who address a global readership and who are not
easily categorized in traditional national-literary terms.) Building on her
literary success, she launched herself on a second career as a political
activist, writing polemical essays against India’s big dam-building projects
and the nuclear bomb (“The Cost of Living,” 1999), and against the
globalization of the energy industry (Power Politics, 2001). Critics on the
left have questioned the integrity of her positions, suggesting that it is more
her celebrity status than her engagement that is at stake; critics on the right
have properly queried her consistent antiwesternism. 6 Yet
aside from the ambiguities of her political position, her writing is noteworthy
insofar as the style itself testifies to underlying predispositions: her own
and, hypothetically, those of the movement against globalization more broadly.
By looking closely at Roy’s writings, we can inquire into the character of
antiglobalization.
Roy’s
public discourse tends to replace reasoned argument with affective performance.
Indeed she frequently makes emotional responses her topic, rather than the
phenomena that elicit those responses. She simultaneously flaunts an
exaggerated affect of her own. Thus, for example, in the midst of an otherwise expository
essay, she breaks out into the cry “. . . hear the thrumming, the deadly
drumbeat of burgeoning anger. Please. Please, stop the war now.”7 In
this case she is referring to the Afghanistan war and the erroneous expectation
that it would elicit enormous resistance, leading to a disastrous outcome comparable
to that of the Soviet invasion. Yet the issue here is not that she was wrong in
this particular instance (as she may be in others). What is remarkable is her
stylistic readiness to shift out of a modicum of rational debate into an
overwrought language of direct address, threat, and exaggeration. She allows her
writing to become so emotional, however, because her analysis is itself focused
on questions of affective response: she is less concerned with facts or
political processes than with sentiments and psychological predispositions. Her
ultimate topic is subjectivity, and she addresses it in a subjective manner.
Thus we find her dwelling on the “prevailing paranoia,” and the “raging emotions
[that] are being let loose into the world.”8 It
follows then that she characterizes the U.S. population not in terms of any
imaginable analysis of political interests or traditions— its attitudes are not
taken that seriously—or in terms of political parties or competing candidates
but solely as the victim of an emotional manipulation. Political slogans “are
cynically doled out by government spokesmen like a daily dose of vitamins or anti-depressants.
Regular medication ensures that mainland America continues to remain the enigma
it has always been—a curiously insular people, administered by a pathologically
meddlesome promiscuous government.”9 This
fear of promiscuity, already identified in Baudrillard’s account, will recur in
our reading of Roy. The discourse of antiglobalization seems to be carried by
the imagery of contamination. For now, suffice it to note this congruence of
hypersubjectivism and anti-Americanism. The enormous threat that she imagines
America to pose is not substantiated in political terms, where it might be
debated; it is turned instead into emotion and affect.
As
with other critics of U.S. foreign policy, Roy refuses to ask whether there
might be some rationality in the U.S. political consensus. Instead, she resorts
to the thesis of a totally manipulated public, driven by emotion and devoid of
reason. Emotion trumps argument, but this verdict that she directs at the
American public is in fact an appropriate characterization of her own speech.
Hence the relative absence of any economic theory (which might have been
expected in the discussion of major economic phenomena) and the curious
confusion of categories in the political discussion: she can never quite
explain if she is arguing for more state regulation of the economy or for less
state bureaucracy in order to diminish corruption. She rarely gets to this
point of clarification, and her refusal to develop rational argument drives a
further prominent feature of her essayistic prose: the stylistic preference for
rhetorical questions, indeed, frequently the string of rhetorical questions—a
gesture that allows her to pretend that she possesses a simple answer, which others
ought to know already, while absolving her of an obligation to divulge the
presumed answer and defend it with argument.
This
series of questions therefore amounts to a rhetoric of arrogance, the goal of
which is presumably to counterfeit a logical high ground, but the result is the
constant demonstration of the limits of her thinking. Even positively predisposed
and wellmeaning readers can only be disappointed by her constant refusal to
follow through on a line of argument.
Her
writing displays a marked preference for blanket dismissiveness and innuendo.
References to the free press or the free market are placed in quotation marks,
to indicate denigration, without ever elaborating on the problem suggested: an easy
way to convey a hostile stance without accepting the responsibility of
explaining why she thinks a free press and a free market are not desirable
institutions. Similarly, she has a propensity to indicate the policies she
opposes by personalizing them, associating them with typically unnamed figures
whom she briefly describes in derogatory ways, a strategy designed to establish
a cozy relationship of prejudice with her reader. As discussed in chapter 3,
she conjures up at one point “a marrowy American panelist” at a conference; no
other panelist is described, nor is any member of another nation given this
sort of physical presence.10 In a separate passage,
another American is described as “rolling his R’s in his North American way,”
as if having an accent were the crime.11 More
important than her claims regarding the policies she opposes—and these claims never
even rise to the level of coherent argument—is this strategy to personalize and
demean her opponent rhetorically: as if the pronunciation or the body type
alone were sufficient grounds to reject the stance associated with anonymous
American individuals. Her rhetorical success, however, lies precisely in her
propagandistic ability to establish this anti-American bond with her readers:
not based on policy debate but through hostile caricatures of accent and
physical appearance.
This
direction of animosity toward individuals because of physical appearance,
accent, and nationality is an expression of the strategy of stereotyping and
racialization that pervades Roy’s prose in multiple ways. In some cases, it is
quite pronounced and polemical. Thus, for example, in her attack on the Indian
development of nuclear weapons, she deftly redirects the reader’s anger away
from India or the Indian government that developed the weapon and toward the
presumed real culprit: the white race. “[Nuclear weapons] are purveyors of
madness. They are the ultimate colonizer. Whiter than any white man that ever lived.
The very heart of whiteness.”12 The Indian nuclear arsenal is,
apparently, not the fault of the Indian government but of the westerners who
invented the weapons. Indeed she not only insists that it was the West, (i.e.,
the United States) that initiated the nuclear arms race, but she also goes on
to make nuclear weaponry identical with a racial enemy: it is the opponent’s
corporeal difference that elicits hatred. Hence her explicit condemnation of
the West: “These are people whose histories are spongy with the blood of
others. . . . They have plundered nations, snuffed out civilizations,
exterminated entire populations.” 13 One
looks in vain for nuance in the judgment; instead one finds the blanket
condemnation of the white West (as if the West were solely white) as a whole,
which stands as a universal and ineluctable threat.
The
only alternative, for Roy, seems to lie in the idealized self-sufficiency of
the village past.14 Absolute identity, without foreign
presence, without external exchange, and without modernization, amounts to the
antiglobal utopia, and it stands in contrast to the infinite threats associated
with the outside world. This infinite menace, exuded by the all-powerful West,
takes the form of the all-destructive bomb and assaults mind and body in what
is ultimately the expression of a paranoid worldview: unlimited danger is
always everywhere. The only possible safety is in a retreat to the absolute
origin of undifferentiation.
This
worldview, the search for an absolute self-identity and the rejection of
outside forces as always only destructive, finds its fullest expression in
Roy’s novel The God of
Small Things. Although the book does touch on some
political matters— Indian Communism, the labor movement, the relationship to colonialism—it
is not primarily a tendentious or explicitly engaged novel; it therefore stands
at odds with Roy’s polemical essays, which are very much directed toward a
political public sphere. In particular, it would be difficult to say that The God of Small Things takes
an explicit position on globalization, except perhaps in the peripheral
denigration of tourism; this, however, is only a minor part of the novel.
Nonetheless, as a whole it is in fact driven by a logic that corroborates the
antiglobalization of Roy’s engagement elsewhere and that therefore can serve as
a further indication of the tendencies and pressures at stake in the critique
of globalization. On multiple levels, one finds the constant celebration of
indigenous nativist substance and the corollary denunciation of all that is
foreign. The strident antiwesternism and the hatred of whiteness evidenced in
her essays are very much compatible with the substance of the novel.
In
terms of aesthetic culture, two key events structure the work: the fictional
family’s visit to a cinema to see The Sound of Music
and a performance of traditional Indian kathakali dance. The former
scene turns into a site of depravity—not the film itself, but the foyer of the
theater where the young boy is molested. Roy depicts modernity, at least the
modernity of Western cinema, as the site of perversion. In contrast, kathakali is
presented as the opposite of tourism, the source of a cultural authenticity
that opposes the forms of the Western culture industry. Roy conveys an
aesthetic program of familiarity and community—precisely the antipode to
cinematic suspense: “It didn’t matter that the story had begun, because
kathakali discovered long ago that the secret of the Great Stories is that they
have no secrets. The Great
Stories are the ones you have heard and want to hear again.”15 The
organic communalism of traditional dance performance is mobilized as an
alternative to touristic commercialism and to the degradation of entertainment cinema.
The move is reminiscent of other celebrations of oral cultures in literary
criticism, in particular, the literary critic Walter Benjamin’s suggested
opposition between story-telling and novel-writing.16 Yet
while Benjamin emphasized the moment of community as an alternative to a lonely
and isolated individuality, Roy pushes the model in another direction, toward
the assertion of the positive value of familiarity. Her point is not community,
or—more bluntly—collectivized communalism, as for Benjamin, but the maintenance
of a pure homogeneity. Her cultural program is a return: to that which is not
foreign, to family and the familiar, a return ultimately to native soil and native
blood. Her critique of globalization turns into the fear of the foreign.
As a
whole, the plot of the novel therefore necessarily involves a return to the
native village. In terms of the family structure that organizes the fiction,
the erotic relations between Indians and Western foreigners all end in failure.
The God of Small Things might
easily, and appropriately, be read as a denunciation of miscegenation. The
novel suggests that the whiteness that Roy otherwise condemns is incompatible
with the Indian body. This sexualized xenophobia draws attention to how a typically
left-wing antiglobalization sentiment can overlap with a sometimes right-wing
hostility to immigration, since both are concerned with the integrity of
borders. In Roy’s novel, Rahel’s brief marriage to an American is particularly
insipid and shortlived, while Chacko’s marriage to an Englishwoman ends in divorce,
and their only child drowns. In a moment of particular cruelty, the novel
concludes with a sexualized humiliation of the bereaved mother. Other
encounters with the West are similarly degraded, including a dalliance between
the aunt and a Catholic priest. Throughout the novel, moreover, tourism
corrupts: the son of a Communist figure, bearing the name “Lenin,” fears that this
nomenclature may offend Western foreigners and therefore masquerades as
“Levin.” The Jewish name is associated with the West and represents a
humorously diminutive contrast to the threatening revolutionary reference
“Lenin.” The antisemitism of this labeling lies in the suggestion of
inferiority, the presentation of the Jewish name as meek in contrast to the
heroic “Lenin.” Meanwhile the Anglophilia of the central family remains the novel’s
major problem. Apparently, for Roy, nothing good ever came of study abroad or
foreign spouses.
Although
foreignness is the problem, the solution lies in the search for an absolute
local identity: this is the cultural program that mirrors antiglobalization.
The colonial mentality of yearning for Britain gives way to a new feeling of
being at home in India. Yet for Roy, this goes far beyond decolonization. That search
for identity leads to the novel’s culmination in the incestuous love of the two
twins, Rahel and Esta—a desire for endogamy as Roy’s extreme expression of the
fear of globalization.
Promiscuity
(Baudrillard’s problem too, as we have seen) evidently includes any marrying
outside of the native culture. In contrast, the love affair with Indian
culture, staged particularly in the kathakali dance, betrays a narcissism that
culminates in self-love, the corollary to which is the hatred of the other. Hence,
the contempt for the outside world, the disdain for Anglophilia, and the
requirement that the novel kill off the halfbreed child of the mixed marriage.
No family ties between England and India are allowed to survive as the children
of mixed relations die off. Hence also the historical frame that is placed
analytically around the novel’s investigation. The problem, so the narrator
asserts, began long before the plot itself: “. . . it actually began thousands
of years ago. Long before the Marxists came. Before the British took Malabar,
before the Dutch Ascendency” and so forth. Indeed the claim is made that it
preceded all such imperialism and “that it really began in the days when the
Love Laws were made. The laws that lay down who should be loved and how. And
how much.”17 To be sure, the chronology does not erase the
imperialist legacy for Roy, but an original sin precedes all such occupations.
The “laws of love” pertain to prohibitions of love across castes—the affair between
the protagonist Ammu, and the untouchable Velutha— but also the taboo against
incest. The latter is at the core of the logic: the anthropological mandate to
exogamy generates a pressure to disrupt original identity, and the resistance
to that pressure turns into the paranoid fear of the exterior and of
foreignness.
Hostility
to the outside is the indirect expression of erotic attraction to the other,
which has to be suppressed. Roy’s novel has the advantage of making clear the
psychological and cultural forces at operation in the mentality of
antiglobalization and its proximity to xenophobia.
Baudrillard
and Roy seem to present different accounts of antiglobalization. For
Baudrillard, it is a matter of opposition to the force of total uniformity; for
Roy, a nationalistic resentment against foreignness. Yet these are ultimately
just two sides of the same coin, linked moreover to a generalized resentment
against modernization, development, and capitalism. Anti-Americanism is the
result. In order to sort through some of these issues, it is helpful to turn to
an older tradition, the “Critical Theory” of the Frankfurt School, especially
the writings of the German philosopher Theodor Adorno. Classical Critical
Theory was nothing if not an inquiry into the genealogy of fanaticism as a
political and social-psychological phenomenon, both with regard to the virulence
of fascist movements in the 1930s and to aspects of student movements in the
1960s. For all the obvious differences, there were deep similarities,
particularly in the overlap of anti-Americanism and hostility to modernization.
Before
approaching Adorno’s cultural judgments, it is important to point out some
undeniable limitations of Critical Theory, especially with regard to
globalization and other objective social and economic processes. The Frankfurt
School inherited many of Marxism’s failings, especially an underdeveloped interest
in the institutional relationship of the state to the market; descriptions of
social processes were based primarily on ideological claims and the political
program, rather than on empirical observation or genuine data. In particular,
the question of the relationship between the political and economic sectors of
modern society was treated with enormous oversimplification. For classical
Marxism, there was ultimately no separate political or public sphere, since
state action was treated as always mirroring ruling class economic interest:
hence the predisposition to propose deterministic accounts of society and an
inability to address questions of practice, at least in mainstream Marxism. If
one assumes that everything is only economics, there is little room for
independent political considerations.
However,
this reductionist treatment of politics as merely economics in disguise took on
a new color during the second third of the twentieth century, marked as it was
by various examples of massive state intervention in the economy. It is tempting
to venture the claim that the expansive state of the era of National Socialism
and Stalinism was a serendipitous topic for Critical Theory’s Marxism, since in
those instances, the opportunity to distinguish between market and state was in
fact minimal. The older Marxist vice of treating the political sphere as the
direct function of economics suddenly turned into a virtue in an era in which
state intervention in the economy had expanded enormously. In this context of
extensive state regulation (in totalitarian regimes, of course, much more than
in Western, democratic welfare states, but there as well), the question of the
distinction between state and market became less pronounced.
Just
as classical nineteenth-century Marxism had had little to say about the state
or the specificity of politics, early twentieth-century Critical Theory had
even less to say about the specificity of economics. In any case, this
intellectual history clearly demonstrates the limits of the pertinence of
Critical Theory to the objective economic discussion of globalization, be it with
regard to the empirical processes of political economy or the policy questions
associated with regulation and deregulation.
However,
while Critical Theory has little to contribute to empirical social-scientific
analysis or economic policy (but of course neither do the competing models of
cultural theory, neo-Marxism and post-structuralism, at the beginning of the
twenty-first century), it is nonetheless useful in the interrogation of the overlapping
fields of antiglobalization and anti-Americanism. Our terrain of inquiry
therefore shifts from the primary question of globalization as the economic
consequence of the international market in goods and services to another set of
issues: the cultural consequences of globalization and, in particular, the emergence
of the prominent and complex discourse of antiglobalization.
Why
has antiglobalization taken the place of Communist anticapitalism? If
globalization in fact produces so much wealth, why does it elicit so much
opposition? Or more pointedly: how and why does antiglobalization inherit the
hostility to modernization that has motivated earlier protest movements? Such a
rejection is often associated with stereotypical anti-Americanism and
frequently with antisemitism as well. Approaching the globalization debate as a
cultural rather than an economic matter invites an analysis parallel to the
cultural criticism of Nazism carried out by Critical Theory. The framework of
this essay is too narrow to reconstruct the full range of the Frankfurt School’s
accounts of fascism and antisemitism, or even their sparse comments on the
state and economy. Still it is illuminating to contrast some of Adorno’s more
pointed analyses, especially in the volume Stichworte (Catchwords),18 with
the paradigmatic critiques of globalization exemplified by the writings of
Baudrillard and Roy. What does Critical Theory suggest with regard to the
particular psychology of antiglobalization?
The
question is pertinent because the discontent with modernity that Critical
Theory identified in fascism and antisemitism has reappeared today in the
movement against globalization. Published in 1969, Stichworte was the last volume of Adorno’s work that he
was able to oversee before his death, and it includes some of the seminal
analyses on the intersection of politics and culture. At the center of the
volume are three essays that define his legacy with regard to our current
concerns: the standing of national identity, the relationship of Germany and Europe
to the United States, and the question of postfascist culture. Frankfurt School
thinking revolves particularly around the last point: a judgment on the
possibilities of culture and politics in the wake of National Socialism and the
Holocaust. The essay “Education after Auschwitz” puts forward both a fragmentary
social psychology of the mentality that supported the Nazi regime and a program
for a pedagogy against cruelty. Although classical and orthodox Marxism, from
which Critical Theory diverged, emphasized claims about the so-called
developmental laws of capitalism and Lenin’s theory of revolution, Adorno was concerned
with the failure of revolutionary projects, the paradoxical motivation of
populations to support fascism, and their attraction to opting against freedom.
How can we explain the attraction exercised by brutality, domination, and
tyrannical authority? His answers are in many ways framed by his own historical
context, the experience of the Hitler regime, the growing knowledge of the
terror of Stalinism, and his encounter with the mass-cultural democracy of the
United States of the 1940s. Yet what remains particularly compelling is his
criticism of underlying processes of forced collectivism and his corollary identification
of the antidote in an insistence on autonomous individuality. Adorno’s dialectic
of individuality and collectivism, forged in the statist and Fordist era of the
midcentury, takes on a renewed urgency in the context of late twentieth-century
debates between neoliberalism and antiglobal anticapitalism.
Consider
Adorno’s diagnosis of the capacity of individuals to participate in the
persecution of others. Formulated with direct reference to the Holocaust, his
explanation does not involve assertions of long-standing prejudice, tragic
flaws in German culture, or the sort of allegedly atavistic ethnic hatred with
which journalists glossed the wars in the Balkans. Instead, he describes a
modern social psychology. The overarching integration of society, a forced
conformism like the Nazi Gleichschaltung, the
consolidation of institutional power under Hitler, undermines the vitality of
local institutions and individual personalities.
Free
space for free people dwindles away. “The pressure exerted by the prevailing
universal on everything particular, upon the individual people and the
individual institutions, has a tendency to destroy the particular and the
individual together with their power of resistance. With the loss of their
identity and power of resistance, people also forget those qualities by virtue
of which they are able to pit themselves against what at some moment might lure
them again to commit atrocity. Perhaps they are hardly able to offer resistance
when the established authorities once again give them the order, so long as it
is in the name of some ideal in which they half or not at all believe.”19 The
collectivization of society (i.e., the massive expansion of the state into
previously unregulated spheres of social life) weakens local identity
structures, which then become ever more susceptible to a renewed participation
in brutality: it becomes all the more likely that one will just follow orders.
In other words, a general, nearly inescapable so-called rationalization of
society is the precondition for unreasonable and irrational behavior. The more
everything falls under some central control, the more civilization declines.
For Adorno, the civilizing ability of society depends above all on the
particularity of individuals rather than on the framing institutions of social
control.
Human
accomplishments result from individual integrity, not from normative
regulation. However, as the collectivizing state subverts the integrity of
individuals—for Adorno a historical process, the inexorable inevitability of
which he surely overstated in a way that, in retrospect, seems typical for midtwentieth-century
critics of a conformist modernity—individuals lose the power to resist
invitations to take part in cruelty. Understanding how to promote such a
resistance is, for Adorno, the sine qua non of any “education after Auschwtiz.”
The real alternative to totalitarianism is individual integrity.
For
our purposes, it is important to determine how Adorno’s insistence on
individualism as the vehicle for resistance to conformism can be mapped onto
the terrain of globalization and antiglobalization. The alternative to
conformism (the consequence of an expansive state) is not some better
conformism but rather the opposite: a strengthened individuality and the consistent
rejection of all collectivisms. “I think the most important way to confront the
danger of a recurrence [of Auschwitz] is to work against the brute predominance
of all collectives, to intensify the resistance to it by concentrating on the
problem of collectivization. That is not as abstract as it sounds in view of the
passion with which especially young and progressively minded people desire to
integrate themselves into something or other.”20 Protest
movements, in other words, may just reproduce the conformism against which they
seemed to be opposed. For Adorno, the solution does not lie in the assertion of
a minority group identity against a majority identity, or even in the evocation
of a collective solidarity with a suffering group. Collectivized solidarity, on
the contrary, is—owing to its collectivism— antithetical to human compassion, which
depends instead on the possibility of individual sensibility. The best way to
work against a repetition of Auschwitz is to oppose collectivist mentalities and
the structures, be they political, cultural, or psychological, that support
them.
Adorno’s
Critical Theory is significant for contemporary discussions in two distinct
ways. First, it entails the critique of a blind activism. Even admirable ideals
can be discredited by their flawed pursuit; the ends do not justify the means.
His criticism of the West German student movement of the 1960s remains relevant
to aspects of the antiglobalization movement and its propensity to engage in
street violence and vandalism, as became clear in the riots in Seattle and
Genoa. Second, with regard to the problem of a homogenizing collectivism,
Adorno’s vision tilts very much toward the defense of the individual against
the state—and is hence objectively neoliberal, no matter how anachronistic that
term may be for the analysis of Adorno in his historical context. The logic of
Adorno’s critique of totalitarianism implies the desideratum of a smaller
state, not expanded regulation: more individualistic entrepreneurs, fewer regulatory
agencies. This however suggests that his thinking is orthogonal to the central
motif of antiglobalization, the appeal for greater regulation of the market, be
it in the form of “local” protectionism or through international bureaucracies
and agreements.
In
the end, the defense of autonomy and particularity means that Adorno’s implied
economic theory—despite his Marxist background—is closer to Hayek than to
Stiglitz. Adorno’s defense of individualism against collectivism pervades the
following two essays in Stichworte,
which should be read in relation to each other: “On the Question: What Is German”
and “Scientific Experiences of a European Scholar in America.” The two texts
convey Adorno’s complex relations to both German and American culture, marked
by the characteristic ambivalence of affection for and critique of each. The
two essays, read together, explore the antinomies of modern culture, the
philosophical humanities that define Adorno’s German world, and the empirical
social science of the United States. As is well known, Adorno remained deeply
critical of that empiricism, and he was always more at home in the world of
German speculative thought than in modern quantitative social science.
His
unexpectedly warm account of his American experience is, therefore, even more
striking. His evaluation of America pertains to the globalization discussion to
the extent that the latter is largely about the United States and an
anti-Americanism that Adorno, for all his high-culture mandarinism, never
endorsed. In other words, Adorno had all the European high-cultural biases that
might have made him an elitist anti-American; instead, however, he expressed
approval for American culture and denounced the German anti-Americanism of the
1960s.
Yet
even more important than deciphering his particular judgment on the United
States or Europe is identifying the underlying rationale. Anglo-American
individualism, he suggests, generated a greater capacity to resist fascism than
was ever the case in continental Europe. Continental Europe, in contrast, remained
deeply defined by a culture of authoritarianism. (He does not distinguish much
within Europe, unfortunately; nonetheless, the distinction between European
culture on the one hand, and the Anglo-American world on the other, repeats the
polarity we could observe in Brecht’s wartime reflections discussed in chapter
3.) Hence his analyses of the German predisposition to dismiss or even denounce
American culture as too superficial, commercial, or insignificant. He reaches
back to the notorious case of the Germanophile Houston Stewart Chamberlain, who
left his native England to marry into the Wagner family. (Adorno’s move to
explore German nationalism by examining a British expatriate exemplifies
Critical Theory’s program of de-essentializing national identity: the most
voluble German was not really German at all.) Chamberlain’s hostile judgment on
Anglo-American culture, characteristically racialized in the form of
antisemitism, is—for Adorno, the Marxist— the effect not of a genuinely
different social model, not of an authentic distinction between two national
traditions, but rather of a relative underdevelopment within the fundamentally
identical process of economic modernization. Germans, or a Germanophile like
Chamberlain, could celebrate continental Europe against the commercialism of
England only because the continental economy was relatively, if only minimally,
backward. It would soon catch up, but in the meantime the apparent distinction
in the degree of commercialism could be misunderstood to indicate profound
cultural distinctions. The result of this economic backwardness was the
antimodernist and antisemitic populist discourse of German cultural superiority
over Anglo-American commercialism.
Adorno
rejects that European ideology, especially its reductionist account of a merely
venal Anglo-American world. On the contrary, he associates American advanced
capitalism emphatically with an aspiration to freedom that, so he claims, takes
on a practical character in real-world efforts to promote freedom, in contrast
to the merely philosophical freedom of continental philosophy: “Following a
tradition of hostility to civilization that is older than Spengler, one feels
superior to the other continent because it has produced nothing but
refrigerators and automobiles while Germany produced the culture of the spirit.
. . . In America, however, in the omnipresent for-other all the way to keep smiling,
there also flourishes sympathy, compassion, and commiseration with the lot of
the weaker. The energetic will to establish a free society—rather than only
apprehensively thinking of freedom and, even in thought, degrading it into
voluntary submission—does not forfeit its goodness because the societal system
imposes limits on its realization. In Germany, arrogance toward America is
inappropriate.”21 The impropriety of that arrogance is not primarily
about the history of the Second World War or the notion of some obligatory
gratitude for the American defense of West Germany during the cold war.
For
Adorno, the issue is rather the difference between the American culture of
freedom, on the one hand, and the German, or more broadly European, regime of
regulatory statism, on the other. Adorno’s politics are consistent on this
point. This is why he has long been rejected by the German Left for his
anticollectivism and by the German nationalist Right for his pro-Americanism. Not
only his positive judgment on the United States but, more important, his
philosophical admonition against collectivized identity structures help clarify
the ideology of antiglobalization, just as they shed useful light on the
growing difference in values between continental Europe and the United States,
the end of the so-called community of values, the allegedly shared ideals that
united the United States and Western Europe in the cold war transatlantic
alliance.
This
is not the place to try to make sense of all the tensions within Adorno’s
thought, especially the balancing act between his Marxist legacy and his
anti-Communism. That constellation of ideas is, to say the least, complex. For
our purposes here, however, it suffices to note that several of the predominant
motifs in some of Adorno’s work retain relevance in the face of antiglobalization:
the defense of American individualism against European collectivism, the
suspicion of regimes of statist regulation, a skepticism toward the conformist
group identities in activist youth movements (regardless of their ideals), and
a wariness of the prominent antisemitism in antimodernist protest movements.
The point is certainly not that all these characteristics recur uniformly
throughout the antiglobalization movement but that they recur with enough
frequency to be worrisome. In this sense Adorno’s analysis of fascist and
postfascist antimodernism— the point at which the “authoritarian personality”
recurs in the presumably antiauthoritarian protest movement—has significance for
the understanding of contemporary antiglobalization and its anti-American
message.
Critical
Theory’s historical analysis of fascism and authoritarian predispositions in
the past—the antimodernism of fascism or the 1960s counterculture—is certainly
not the same as the critical-theoretical consideration of antiglobalization
today. The differences in context are significant. Yet the understanding of historical
fascism as an anticapitalist and antimodernist protest with cultural and
psychological corollaries suggests parallels to the ideological texture of
contemporary antiglobalization sentiment: the fear of the free market, the
anxiety about mobility, the celebration of indigenousness, and the totalizing
fear of an external threat. Whatever the progressive pretenses of
antiglobalization, its repressive potential is clear. Antiglobalization is deeply
fearful of freedom and therefore becomes hostile to the institutions and
symbols of freedom. The conclusion to draw from these observations is not that
it is wrong or impossible to criticize aspects of the international economy. On
the contrary, neither Baudrillard nor Roy appears to have given serious
attention to the international economy and its consequences. What their
writings nonetheless demonstrate are some of the problematic dynamics that
operate in the culture of antiglobalization and that explain its turn toward
anti-Americanism. Adorno’s critique of anti-Americanism and his analysis of the
cultural consequences of collectivism shed important light on these features of
anti-globalization today.
1.
Jean Baudrillard, Power Inferno (Paris:
Galile´e, 2002), 67.
2.
Cf. ibid., 72.
3.
Jean Baudrillard, “The Spirit of Terrorism,” trans. Kathy Ackerman, Telos 121 (Fall 2001), 135.
4.
Baudrillard, Power Inferno,
83.
5.
Baudrillard, “The Spirit of Terrorism,” 134.
6.
Ramachandra Guha, “The Arun Shourie of the Left,” The Hindu Nov.
26, 2000; Ian Buruma, “The Anti-American,” The New
Republic Online, March 17, 2003, http://www.tnr.com.
7.
Arundhati Roy, Power Politics (Cambridge:
South End Press, 2001), 140.
8.
Ibid., 139.
9.
Ibid., 144.
10.
Ibid., 41.
11.
Ibid., 36.
12.
Arundhati Roy, The Cost of Living (New
York: Modern Library, 1999), 101.
13.
Ibid., 112.
14.
Ibid., 53.
15.
Arundhati Roy, The God of Small Things (New
York: Harper, 1998), 218.
16.
Cf. Walter Benjamin, “The Storyteller,” in Illuminations,
ed. Hannah Arendt (New York: Schocken, 1968), 83–110.
17.
Roy, The God of Small Things, 33.
18.
Theodor W. Adorno, Critical
Models: Interventions and Catchwords, trans. Henry
W. Pickford (New York: Columbia University Press, 1998). This volume includes
translations of the two separate German volumes named in the subtitle.
19.
Ibid., 193–194.
20.
Ibid., 197.
21.
Ibid., 210.
==============================
Aburish,
Said K. Saddam Hussein: The Politics of Revenge. London: Bloomsbury,
2000.
Addison,
Joseph. “The Campaign, A Poem to His Grace the Duke of Marlborough, 1705. The Penn State Archive of Samuel Johnson’s Lives of Poets,
ed. Kathleen Nulton Kemmerer. http:// www.hn.psu.edu.faculty/kkemmerer/poets/addison/
campaign.htm.
Adorno,
Theodor W. Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords. Trans.
Henry W. Pickford. New York: Columbia University Press, 1998.
Al-Khalil,
Samir [Kanan Makiya, pseud.]. The Monument:
Art, Vulgarity and Responsibility in Iraq. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1991.
Arendt,
Hannah. The Origins of Totalitarianism.
New York: Harcourt, 1968.
Baudrillard,
Jean. Power Inferno. Paris:
Galile´e, 2002.
———.
“The Spirit of Terrorism.” Trans. Kathy Ackerman. Telos 121 (Fall 2001): 134–42.
Benjamin,
Walter. “The Storyteller.” In Illuminations,
trans. Harry Zohn, ed. Hannah Arendt. New York: Schocken, 1968.
Berman,
Russell A. Cultural Studies of Modern Germany: History,
Representation, and Nationhood. Madison: University of
Wisconsin Press, 1993.
Bohrer,
Karl Heinz. “Provinzialismus (II): ein Psychogramm.” Merkur 45, no. 3 (March 1991): 255–61.
Brecht,
Bertolt. Journals, 1934–1955. Trans. Hugh
Rorrison. New York: Routledge, 1996.
Broder,
Henryk M. Kein Krieg, Nirgends: Die Deutschen und der Terror. Berlin:
Berlin Verlag, 2002.
Buruma,
Ian. “The Anti-American.” The New
Republic Online. March 17, 2003. http://www.tnr.com.
Bush,
George H. W. “Address to the Nation Announcing the Deployment of United States
Armed Forces to Saudi Arabia.” August 8, 1990.
———.
“Remarks to Department of Defense Employees.” August 15, 1990.
———.
“Remarks at a Republican Campaign Rally in Manchester, New Hampshire.” October
23, 1990.
Chicago
Council on Foreign Relations and German Marshall Fund of the United States. Worldviews 2002: Comparing American and European Public Opinion on
Foreign Policy. 2002. http:// www.worldviews.org.
Diner, Dan. America in the Eyes of the Germans: An Essay on Anti-Americanism. Trans.
Allison Brown. Princeton: Markus Wiener, 1996. Enzensberger, Hans Magnus.
“Hitler’s Successor: Saddam Hussein in the Context of German History.” Trans.
Mary Strand. Telos 86 (Winter
1990–91): 153–57.
Goethe,
Johann Wolfgang. “Wilhelm Meisters Lehrjahre.” In: Goethe’s Werke, Vol. 7., ed. Erich Trunz. Hamburg: Christian
Wegner Verlag, 1962.
Guha,
Ramachandra. “The Arun Shourie of the Left.” The Hindu (Madras), November 26, 2000.
Habermas, Ju¨rgen, et al. “Das
alte Europa antwortet Herrn Rumsfeld.” Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, January 24,
2003.
Hamza,
Khidir. Saddam’s Bombmaker: The Terrifying Story of the
Iraqi Nuclear and Biological Weapons Agenda. New York: Scribner,
2000. Hitler, Adolf. Mein Kampf.
Trans. Ralph Manheim. London: Hutchinson, 1969.
Ju¨nger,
Ernst. “Der Kampf als inneres Erelbnis.” In Sa¨mtliche Werke, Essays I: Betrachtungen zur Zeit. Stuttgart:
Klett Verlag, 1980.
Kaufman,
Robert. “Aura, Still.” October,
no. 99 (Winter 2002): 45–80.
Khadduri,
Majid. Independent Iraq: A Study in Iraqi Politics.
London: Oxford University Press, 1960.
Luka´cs,
Georg. The Theory of the Novel: A Historico-Philosophical
Essay on the Forms of Great Epic Literature. Trans. Anna
Bostock. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1971.
Macaulay,
Thomas Babbington. “The Life and Writings of Addison.” In Macaulay, Essays on Milton and Addison. New York:
Longmans, Green, and Co., 1900.
Makiya,
Kanan. Cruelty and Silence: War, Tyranny, Uprising, and
the Arab World. New York: Norton, 1994.
———.
Republic of Fear. Los Angeles:
University of California Press, 1998.
Mann,
Thomas. Achtung, Europa! 1933–1938.
Frankfurt am Main: S. Fischer, 1995.
Minc,
Alain. “Terrorism of the Spirit.” Trans. Kathy Ackerman. Telos 121 (Fall 2001): 143–45.
Moran,
Daniel. “Restraints on Violence and the Reconstruction of International Order
after 1945.” In War and Terror,
ed. Frank Trommler and Michael Geyer. Washington: American Institute for
Contemporary German Studies. Forthcoming.
Natteau,
Nicholas. Saddam over Iraq: How Much Longer? A Study of the
Ba’thist Destruction of Iraqi Civil Society and the Prospects for Its Rebirth.
Masters Thesis, Boston University, 1997. www.joric.com/Saddam/Saddam.htm.
Nullis,
Claire. “Report: Arab Economies Need Reform.” Washington Times, September 8, 2002.
Pew
Global Attitudes Project. Views of a
Changing World, June 2003. Washington, D.C.: Pew Research Center for
the People and the Press,
2003.
Revel,
Jean-Franc¸ois. L’obsession
anti-ame´ricaine: Son fonctionnement, ses causes, ses inconse´quences.
Paris: Plon, 2002.
Roger,
Philippe. L’ennemi ame´ricain: Ge´ne´alogie de
l’antiamericanisme franc ¸aise. Paris: Seuil, 2002.
Roy,
Arundhati. The Cost of Living. New York:
Modern Library, 1999.
———.
The God of Small Things. New York:
Harper, 1998.
———.
Power Politics. Cambridge:
South End Press, 2001.
Rushdie,
Salman. “February 2002: Anti-Americanism.” In Rushdie, Step across This Line: Collected Nonfiction 1992–2002.
New York: Random House, 2002.
Safire,
William. “The German Problem,” New York Times,
September 19, 2002. A35.
Shlapentokh,
Vladmir, and Joshua Woods. America’s Image
Abroad. Forthcoming.
Smith,
Tom W., and Lars Jarkko. “National Pride in Cross-National Perspective.” Paper
of the National Opinion Research Center. University of Chicago, April 2001.
http://www.issp.org/ paper.htm.
Zadek,
Peter. “Kulturkampf? Ich bin dabei.” Interview in Der Spiegel, July 14, 2003.
Zantop,
Susan. Colonial Fantasies: Conquest, Family, and Nation in
Precolonial Germany, 1770–1870. Durham: Duke University
Press, 1997.
Zelikow,
Philip, and Condoleezza Rice. Germany Unified
and Europe Transformed: A Study in Statecraft. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1995.
==============================